WAEC GCE Mathematics Question and Answers 2023: Objective “OBJ” And Essay

Photo of Musa FN

The West African Examination Council (WAEC) is set to administer the General Mathematics examination for external candidates of the GCE (General Certificate Examination) in 2023. This article aims to provide candidates with a comprehensive guide to the WAEC GCE Mathematics questions and answers for both the objective and essay sections. It is important to note that this article is not an exam expo or a means to obtain live question papers before the exam. Instead, it serves as a revision guide using likely exam questions from past WAEC Maths papers.

Jamb Fixes Saturday 6th May 2023 for Outstanding Candidates To Sit for Rescheduled UTME Examination

Exam Format and Schedule

The WAEC GCE Mathematics examination will consist of two papers: Paper 1, which is the objective section, and Paper 2, which is the essay section. Here is the schedule for the 2023 WAEC GCE Mathematics exam:

  • Paper 2 (Essay): This paper will start at 9:30 am and last for 2 hours 30 minutes.
  • Paper 1 (Objective): This paper will commence at 2:00 pm and last for 1 hour 30 minutes.

It is crucial for candidates to be familiar with the exam format and schedule to manage their time effectively during the examination.

Note: This article is not a means to obtain live question papers or engage in exam malpractice. All information provided is based on past questions and serves as a revision guide.

Sample Objective “OBJ” Questions

In the objective “OBJ” section of the WAEC GCE Mathematics exam, candidates will be required to shade their answers in the provided answer booklet. Here are some sample objective questions that candidates may encounter:

  • C. -2cos^2θ
  • D. -2sin^2θ

Candidates should thoroughly practice objective questions like these to improve their speed and accuracy in answering them.

Sample Essay Questions

The essay section of the WAEC GCE Mathematics exam requires candidates to write their answers in the provided answer booklet. Here are some sample essay questions that candidates may encounter:

  • (a) Solution:
  • (b) Solution:

Candidates should practice solving essay questions like these to develop their problem-solving skills and enhance their understanding of mathematical concepts.

Tips for Success in the WAEC GCE Maths Exam

To excel in the WAEC GCE Maths exam, candidates should consider the following tips:

  • Familiarize yourself with the exam format and schedule to effectively manage your time during the examination.
  • Practice solving a wide range of objective and essay questions from past papers to improve your problem-solving skills and speed.
  • Review and revise key mathematical concepts, formulas, and techniques.
  • Seek clarification on any topics or concepts you find challenging.
  • Develop a study schedule and allocate sufficient time for each topic.
  • Work on improving your speed and accuracy in solving mathematical problems.
  • Take advantage of online resources, tutorials, and study materials to supplement your preparation.
  • Practice mental calculations and develop shortcuts for solving problems efficiently.
  • Review your answers carefully before submitting the answer booklet.
  • Stay calm and confident during the exam, and trust in your preparation.

Remember, the WAEC GCE Mathematics exam is an opportunity to demonstrate your understanding and application of mathematical concepts. With diligent preparation and consistent practice, you can achieve success in the exam.

Best of luck in your preparation and the upcoming WAEC GCE Maths exam!

Do not fall victim to scammers promising access to exam papers. Stay focused, study diligently, and believe in your abilities.

Photo of Musa FN

Leave a Reply Cancel reply

Your email address will not be published. Required fields are marked *

Save my name, email, and website in this browser for the next time I comment.

Related Articles

mathematics objective and essay

WAEC GCE Exam Timetable Nov/Dec 2023 | 2nd series

Science and Technology Innovation Challenge (STIC)

Nigerian Content and Development Management Board Zata Horar Da Daliban Higher Institution

mathematics objective and essay

FEDERAL UNIVERSITY HEALTH SCEINCE AZARE POST UTME AND SCREENING EXERCICE 2021/2022

mathematics objective and essay

Bauch State University Gadau Release 2022/2023 Second Batch Admission List And Invitation For Physical Screening

mathematics objective and essay

Application for Internship University of Abuja Teaching Hospital 2022

Hukumar shirya jarabawar kammala sakandare ta Afrika ta yamma, WAEC, ta saki sakamakon jarabawar da dalibai suka yi ta shekarar 2021.

An Saki Sakamakon Jarrabawa WAEC ta Shekarar 2021

mathematics objective and essay

WAEC GCE Agricultural Science Practical Specimen Answers 2023

mathematics objective and essay

Indian Government (ICCR) Undergraduate/Postgraduate Scholarships for African Students 2022-2023

mathematics objective and essay

GOMBE STATE UNIVERSITY GOMBE RESUMPTION OF 100 LEVEL STUDENTS // 2022

mathematics objective and essay

Top 20 Best Countries to Study Abroad for Nigerian Students

Gwamnatin Jihar Kano ta Biya Kimanin Million N50 Domin Sakin Jarrabawar NECO

Gwamnatin Jihar Kano ta Biya Kimanin Million N50 Domin Sakin Jarrabawar NECO

Federal University Dutse Fresh Student Registration Guidelines 20222023

Federal University Dutse Fresh Student Registration Guidelines 2022/2023

mathematics objective and essay

25,000+ students realised their study abroad dream with us. Take the first step today

Meet top uk universities from the comfort of your home, here’s your new year gift, one app for all your, study abroad needs, start your journey, track your progress, grow with the community and so much more.

mathematics objective and essay

Verification Code

An OTP has been sent to your registered mobile no. Please verify

mathematics objective and essay

Thanks for your comment !

Our team will review it before it's shown to our readers.

Leverage Edu

  • School Education /

Essay on Importance of Mathematics in our Daily Life in 100, 200, and 350 words.

mathematics objective and essay

  • Updated on  
  • Dec 22, 2023

Essay on Importance of Mathematics in our Daily Life

Mathematics is one of the core aspects of education. Without mathematics, several subjects would cease to exist. It’s applied in the science fields of physics, chemistry, and even biology as well. In commerce accountancy, business statistics and analytics all revolve around mathematics. But what we fail to see is that not only in the field of education but our lives also revolve around it. There is a major role that mathematics plays in our lives. Regardless of where we are, or what we are doing, mathematics is forever persistent. Let’s see how maths is there in our lives via our blog essay on importance of mathematics in our daily life. 

Table of Contents

  • 1 Essay on Importance of Mathematics in our Daily life in 100 words 
  • 2 Essay on Importance of Mathematics in our Daily life in 200 words
  • 3 Essay on Importance of Mathematics in our Daily Life in 350 words

Essay on Importance of Mathematics in our Daily life in 100 words 

Mathematics is a powerful aspect even in our day-to-day life. If you are a cook, the measurements of spices have mathematics in them. If you are a doctor, the composition of medicines that make you provide prescription is made by mathematics. Even if you are going out for just some groceries, the scale that is used for weighing them has maths, and the quantity like ‘dozen apples’ has maths in it. No matter the task, one way or another it revolves around mathematics. Everywhere we go, whatever we do, has maths in it. We just don’t realize that. Maybe from now on, we will, as mathematics is an important aspect of our daily life.

Also Read:- Importance of Internet

Essay on Importance of Mathematics in our Daily life in 200 words

Mathematics, as a subject, is one of the most important subjects in our lives. Irrespective of the field, mathematics is essential in it. Be it physics, chemistry, accounts, etc. mathematics is there. The use of mathematics proceeds in our daily life to a major extent. It will be correct to say that it has become a vital part of us. Imagining our lives without it would be like a boat without a sail. It will be a shock to know that we constantly use mathematics even without realising the same. 

From making instalments to dialling basic phone numbers it all revolves around mathematics. 

Let’s take an example from our daily life. In the scenario of going out shopping, we take an estimate of hours. Even while buying just simple groceries, we take into account the weight of vegetables for scaling, weighing them on the scale and then counting the cash to give to the cashier. We don’t even realise it and we are already counting numbers and doing calculations. 

Without mathematics and numbers, none of this would be possible.

Hence we can say that mathematics helps us make better choices, more calculated ones throughout our day and hence make our lives simpler. 

Also Read:-   My Aim in Life

Essay on Importance of Mathematics in our Daily Life in 350 words

Mathematics is what we call a backbone, a backbone of science. Without it, human life would be extremely difficult to imagine. We cannot live even a single day without making use of mathematics in our daily lives. Without mathematics, human progress would come to a halt. 

Maths helps us with our finances. It helps us calculate our daily, monthly as well as yearly expenses. It teaches us how to divide and prioritise our expenses. Its knowledge is essential for investing money too. We can only invest money in property, bank schemes, the stock market, mutual funds, etc. only when we calculate the figures. Let’s take an example from the basic routine of a day. Let’s assume we have to make tea for ourselves. Without mathematics, we wouldn’t be able to calculate how many teaspoons of sugar we need, how many cups of milk and water we have to put in, etc. and if these mentioned calculations aren’t made, how would one be able to prepare tea? 

In such a way, mathematics is used to decide the portions of food, ingredients, etc. Mathematics teaches us logical reasoning and helps us develop problem-solving skills. It also improves our analytical thinking and reasoning ability. To stay in shape, mathematics helps by calculating the number of calories and keeping the account of the same. It helps us in deciding the portion of our meals. It will be impossible to think of sports without mathematics. For instance, in cricket, run economy, run rate, strike rate, overs bowled, overs left, number of wickets, bowling average, etc. are calculated. It also helps in predicting the result of the match. When we are on the road and driving, mathetics help us keep account of our speeds, the distance we have travelled, the amount of fuel left, when should we refuel our vehicles, etc. 

We can go on and on about how mathematics is involved in our daily lives. In conclusion, we can say that the universe revolves around mathematics. It encompasses everything and without it, we cannot imagine our lives. 

Also Read:- Essay on Pollution

Ans: Mathematics is a powerful aspect even in our day-to-day life. If you are a cook, the measurements of spices have mathematics in them. If you are a doctor, the composition of medicines that make you provide prescription is made by mathematics. Even if you are going out for just some groceries, the scale that is used for weighing them has maths, and the quantity like ‘dozen apples’ has maths in it. No matter the task, one way or another it revolves around mathematics. Everywhere we go, whatever we do, has maths in it. We just don’t realize that. Maybe from now on, we will, as mathematics is an important aspect of our daily life.

Ans: Mathematics, as a subject, is one of the most important subjects in our lives. Irrespective of the field, mathematics is essential in it. Be it physics, chemistry, accounts, etc. mathematics is there. The use of mathematics proceeds in our daily life to a major extent. It will be correct to say that it has become a vital part of us. Imagining our lives without it would be like a boat without a sail. It will be a shock to know that we constantly use mathematics even without realising the same.  From making instalments to dialling basic phone numbers it all revolves around mathematics. Let’s take an example from our daily life. In the scenario of going out shopping, we take an estimate of hours. Even while buying just simple groceries, we take into account the weight of vegetables for scaling, weighing them on the scale and then counting the cash to give to the cashier. We don’t even realise it and we are already counting numbers and doing calculations. Without mathematics and numbers, none of this would be possible. Hence we can say that mathematics helps us make better choices, more calculated ones throughout our day and hence make our lives simpler.  

Ans: Archimedes is considered the father of mathematics.

Related Reads:

Hope you find this information useful. For more information on such informative topics for your school, visit our essay writing and follow Leverage Edu.

' src=

Deepansh Gautam

Leave a Reply Cancel reply

Save my name, email, and website in this browser for the next time I comment.

Contact no. *

mathematics objective and essay

Connect With Us

mathematics objective and essay

25,000+ students realised their study abroad dream with us. Take the first step today.

mathematics objective and essay

Resend OTP in

mathematics objective and essay

Need help with?

Study abroad.

UK, Canada, US & More

IELTS, GRE, GMAT & More

Scholarship, Loans & Forex

Country Preference

New Zealand

Which English test are you planning to take?

Which academic test are you planning to take.

Not Sure yet

When are you planning to take the exam?

Already booked my exam slot

Within 2 Months

Want to learn about the test

Which Degree do you wish to pursue?

When do you want to start studying abroad.

January 2024

September 2024

What is your budget to study abroad?

mathematics objective and essay

How would you describe this article ?

Please rate this article

We would like to hear more.

Have something on your mind?

mathematics objective and essay

Make your study abroad dream a reality in January 2022 with

mathematics objective and essay

India's Biggest Virtual University Fair

mathematics objective and essay

Essex Direct Admission Day

Why attend .

mathematics objective and essay

Don't Miss Out

JAMB AND WAEC

Complete NECO 2023 Mathematics Questions and Answers (Essay and Objective)

NECO 2023 Mathematics Questions and Answers (Essay and Objective):

The National Examination Council (NECO) is a Nigerian examination body that conducts the Senior Secondary Certificate Examination (SSCE) for students in their final year of secondary school. The Mathematics examination is one of the core subjects that students are required to take. In this blog post, we will provide you with some tips and tricks on how to prepare for the NECO 2023 Mathematics examination and provide some sample questions and answers.

  • Wednesday, 2nd August 2023
  • General Mathematics (Objective)
  • 10:00am – 11:45am
  • General Mathematics (Essay)
  • 12:00pm – 2:30pm

OBJECTIVE ANSWERS

01-10: CACCDCDECE

11-20: BBCABADCBB

21-30: ECAAEBECCA

31-40: DADABEEBEB

41-50: EECBCBBDAE

51-60: BEECEAECCC

ESSAY ANSWERS

ovCpX9t

  • Does PTI Offer Computer Engineering Course? O’Level Requirements, Cut off Mark, Semester Courses

9nE8JxQ

Leave a Comment Cancel reply

Save my name, email, and website in this browser for the next time I comment.

This site uses Akismet to reduce spam. Learn how your comment data is processed .

Joberplanet

WAEC Mathematics 2023 Essay/Objective Questions and Answers

Free WAEC Mathematics Questions and Answers for 2023. Are you preparing for the WAEC Mathematics Exam and feeling overwhelmed? Don’t worry, you’re not alone. Thousands of students are in the same boat. In this blog post, we’ll be discussing the most common WAEC Mathematics questions, as well as some tips and tricks to help you ace the exam. Let’s get started with WAEC mathematics expo 2023!

Click Here Now To Chat Us on WhatsApp For Subscription Details

WAEC Mathematics Questions and Answers 2023

Joberplanet Team are right now with the WAEC Mathematics expo question paper. It is under verification and once the verification process is completed, we will go ahead to upload it here. Always reload this page in order to see the answers.

WAEC Mathematic OBJECTIVES (OBJ) ANSWERS Loading

2023 VERIFIED Maths OBJ:…Loading

OBJ Answers Loading…. Please Check back later.

°°°°°°°°°°°°°°°°°°°°°°°°°°°°°°°°°°°°°°°° °°°°°°°°°°°°°°°°°°°°°°°°°°°°°°°°°°°°°°°°

WAEC Mathematic Essay Answers

WAEC Mathematics Questions and Answers 2023 Loading…

Essay Answers Loading…. Please Check back later. °°°°°°°°°°°°°°°°°°°°°°°°°°°°°°°°°°°°°°°°

If you have any questions about the WAEC English theory & Obj 2023, kindly let us know in the comment box.

In conclusion, the WAEC Mathematics Questions and Answers 2023 is a challenging one. However, if you’re equipped with the knowledge of the most common questions, as well as an understanding of tips and tricks for acing the exam, there’s no reason why you can’t do well. So don’t be afraid to put in the hard work and effort and you’ll be sure to get the result that you desire. Good luck!

Related Posts

mathematics objective and essay

WAEC Health Science Questions and Answers 2023 (100% Sure) Theory & Obj Solution [16th May]

mathematics objective and essay

WAEC Basic Electricity Questions and Answers 2023 (100% Sure) Theory & Obj Solution [16th May]

mathematics objective and essay

WAEC Igbo language Questions and Answers 2023 (100% Sure) Theory & Obj Solution [16th May]

mathematics objective and essay

WAEC Hausa language Questions and Answers 2023 (100% Sure) Theory & Obj Solution [16th May]

mathematics objective and essay

WAEC Biology practical Questions and Answers 2023 (100% Sure) Theory Solution [16th May]

mathematics objective and essay

WAEC Yoruba language Questions and Answers 2023 (100% Sure) Theory & Obj Solution [16th May]

Comments are closed.

Type above and press Enter to search. Press Esc to cancel.

  • Search Menu
  • Advance articles
  • Author Guidelines
  • Open Access
  • About Philosophia Mathematica
  • Editorial Board
  • Advertising and Corporate Services
  • Journals Career Network
  • Self-Archiving Policy
  • Dispatch Dates
  • Terms and Conditions
  • Journals on Oxford Academic
  • Books on Oxford Academic

Issue Cover

Article Contents

1. introduction, 2. what is objectivity, 3. two reasons for believing in the objectivity of mathematical knowledge, 4. platonism and the objectivity of mathematical knowledge, 5. evolutionary nativism and the objectivity of mathematical knowledge, 6. enculturated mathematics, 7. conclusion: is mathematical knowledge objective.

  • < Previous

Objectivity in Mathematics, Without Mathematical Objects †

  • Article contents
  • Figures & tables
  • Supplementary Data

Markus Pantsar, Objectivity in Mathematics, Without Mathematical Objects, Philosophia Mathematica , Volume 29, Issue 3, October 2021, Pages 318–352, https://doi.org/10.1093/philmat/nkab010

  • Permissions Icon Permissions

I identify two reasons for believing in the objectivity of mathematical knowledge: apparent objectivity and applications in science. Focusing on arithmetic, I analyze platonism and cognitive nativism in terms of explaining these two reasons. After establishing that both theories run into difficulties, I present an alternative epistemological account that combines the theoretical frameworks of enculturation and cumulative cultural evolution. I show that this account can explain why arithmetical knowledge appears to be objective and has scientific applications. Finally, I will argue that, while this account is compatible with platonist metaphysics, it does not require postulating mind-independent mathematical objects.

Many of the most crucial questions in the philosophy of mathematics concern what mathematical knowledge is like (see, e.g. , [ Benacerraf and Putnam, 1983 ; Shapiro, 2005 ]. Is it analytic or synthetic? Is it necessary or contingent? Does it have content or is it purely formal? And finally, closely related to all of the above, the question this paper will focus on: is mathematical knowledge objective ? That question, like the others, is tightly connected to the question what mathematical knowledge is about . For the area of mathematics that children are taught first, namely arithmetic, this latter question seems like a simple one to answer. Arithmetic is about numbers, more specifically the ordered set of natural numbers |$N={0,1,2,3,\ldots}$|⁠ . But the question what natural numbers are has puzzled philosophers since antiquity (see, e.g. , [ Shapiro, 1997 ] for a review). Clearly numbers are not physical objects; so they must be abstract. But if they are abstract, in what sense do numbers exist? Are they just the result of human conventions, as suggested by, e.g. , Field [1980] ? If not, how can we, as Benacerraf [1973] famously asked, as physical subjects get knowledge of abstract non-physical objects? If mathematical objects exist independently of human conventions and practices, how do we get epistemic access to them, i.e ., how can we establish that our mathematical theories accurately capture the characteristics of mathematical objects? 1 In order to answer that question, we need to specify how mathematical knowledge is possible for human subjects. Thus the question what mathematical knowledge is about is ultimately tightly linked to the question how mathematical knowledge can be acquired .

The foundation of platonist epistemology is that since sense perception can never be about the mathematical objects themselves, knowledge about mathematical objects must be gained through reason ( The Republic , 527a–b). 2 With some exceptions ( e.g. , Mill [1843] , intuitionists like Heyting [1931] and Brouwer [1948] , Wittgenstein [1976] , Field [1980] , and Kitcher [1983] , this platonist view ruled the epistemology of mathematics well into the second half of the twentieth century. But more than that, for both platonists and non-platonists, it seemed that there was a largely uniform way of approaching the epistemology of mathematics. Mathematics was thought of exclusively as a sophisticated, (relatively) mature human ability, and the epistemology of mathematics as mainly a topic for philosophy, with its usual a priori methodology.

Then some unexpected results started to surface from empirical research. It was discovered that agents that were previously not thought to have sufficient reasoning ability, i.e. , non-human animals and human infants, were also able to process quantitative information (see, e.g. , [ Starkey and Cooper, 1980 ; Wynn, 1992 ; Dehaene, 1997/2011 ; Hauser et al. , 2000 ; Cantlon and Brannon, 2006 ; Hunt et al. , 2008 ; Pepperberg, 2012 ; Agrillo, 2015 ]). With paper titles like ‘Addition and subtraction by human infants’ [ Wynn, 1992 ], ‘Arithmetic in newborn chicks’ [ Rugani et al. , 2009 ], and ‘Numerical and arithmetical abilities in non-primate species’ [ Agrillo, 2015 ], there appeared to be two clear emerging messages from empirical cognitive scientists. First, arithmetical ability is not only the domain of sufficiently mature human agents. Second, for progress in explaining the acquisition of arithmetical knowledge, we need to be well-informed concerning the empirical research on quantitative cognition. As I have argued before [ 2014 ; 2015a ; 2018a ; 2019a ], and will be discussed in detail in Section 5, I find the first conclusion unwarranted. The second conclusion, on the other hand, is something I agree with. The account I will be proposing in Section 6 will be heavily based on the state-of-the-art empirical research on quantitative cognition. Indeed, I believe that the quantitative abilities we have as infants and share with non-human animals form a foundation for the development of arithmetical knowledge. But, importantly, those abilities themselves must not be considered to be arithmetical.

This distinction between arithmetical and what I call proto-arithmetical abilities is important to make when we consider the question whether mathematical knowledge is objective. As I will argue, as bad a fit as the idea of infant and (non-human) animal arithmetic seems to be with platonism, the two views share one important characteristic. On both accounts, mathematical knowledge can be considered to be essentially objective. In Section 2, I will provide specific criteria for objectivity, but initially objectivity can be understood as the position that mathematics is not about human conventions. Objectivity is of course central to platonist philosophy of mathematics: the set of truths we accept in mathematics is not a matter of convention (see, e.g. , [ Panza and Sereni, 2013 ]). In one way or another, they are determined by objective, mind-independent criteria. Perhaps less obviously, objectivity of arithmetical knowledge is also an essential characteristic of the nativist view that infants and non-human animals possess arithmetical abilities. 3 But this kind of cognitive nativism appears to be as committed to objectivism as platonism is. Infants and most non-human animals cannot be feasibly thought to adhere to conventions; so whatever their putatively arithmetical ability is, it must be due to biological evolution, ‘hardwired’ into their cognitive architecture. The resulting arithmetical knowledge therefore has to be objective in a strong sense, since it is not determined by conventions or customs. Rather, it is dictated by cognitive capabilities that are independent of the particular surroundings where the infant or animal has been born and raised. 4

In Sections 4 and 5, I argue that both views fail to give a satisfactory explanation why mathematical knowledge is seen to be objective. However, it is at least prima facie plausible that mathematical knowledge is objective. As I show in Section 3, we cannot simply dismiss the widely shared impression among mathematicians (as well as scientists and laypeople) that mathematical knowledge is objective, nor can we dismiss that there is a strong philosophical argument for the objectivity of mathematical knowledge based on mathematical applications in science. What I aim to do in this paper, however, is to show that both the apparent objectivity and the mathematical applications can be explained without assuming that mathematical knowledge is indeed objective in the strong sense of the platonist and nativist views. To establish this, I will argue that we need a finer-grained understanding of the development of mathematical knowledge, with sufficient emphasis on its culturally determined character. The biological origins underdetermine the development of arithmetical and other mathematical knowledge, which makes it crucial to identify and analyze the cultural conditions conducive to the development of mathematics. While this might seem to be a step toward the kind of cultural relativism that conflicts with the apparent objectivity ( e.g. , [ Bloor, 1976 ]), I will argue that this is not the case. Instead, with a proper understanding of the cultural factors in developing early quantitative abilities, I argue that we can explain the reasons behind the apparent objectivity of mathematical knowledge and the applications in science. In particular, I will apply the framework of enculturation as developed by Menary [2015] in explaining how culturally dependent factors influence the development of mathematical cognition and mathematical knowledge.

Before analyzing the characteristics and foundations of mathematical knowledge, it is important to explicate what is meant by ‘objective’. This is a widely studied philosophical question and it is not possible here to go into the details, but it is important to note that mathematical objectivity in modern philosophy has been primarily an epistemological rather than an ontological matter. Tait [2001] traces this to Cantor who wrote:

First, we may regard the whole numbers as real in so far as, on the basis of definitions, they occupy an entirely determinate place in our understanding, are well distinguished from all other parts of our thought and stand to them in determinate relationships, and thus modify the substance of our minds in a determinate way. ([ Cantor, 1883 ], quoted in [ Tait, 2001 ], p. 22]).

It is thus not the existence of some platonic world of mathematical objects, but the characteristics of mathematical thinking that should be the standard for objectivity. If we interpret Cantor’s idea in epistemological terms, mathematical knowledge is objective (if it indeed is objective) because of the determinate role that knowledge about mathematical objects plays in our thinking. As Tait [2001] points out, Cantor’s formulation is heavily psychologistic, and in contemporary literature it is more common to talk about the objectivity of mathematical discourse . But the crucial point is that Cantor moves the focus on objectivity away from being primarily about the existence of mathematical objects. 5

When is a form of discourse objective? According to Tait, ‘Objectivity in mathematics is established when meaning has been specified for mathematical propositions, including existential propositions |$\exists xF(x)$| ’ [ 2001 , p. 22]. But as he also points out here, philosophers have understood this ‘meaning’ in different ways. For Hilbert, the meaning of mathematical propositions was fixed entirely by the axioms of the particular mathematical system [ Zach, 2019 ]. But ever since Gödel [ 1931 ] proved the incompleteness of all formal axiomatic systems of arithmetic, this approach has been untenable. In order to establish meaning, and hence objectivity, something more than agreeing on axioms is needed. Importantly, in the above manner specified by Tait, it would require establishing the meaning of propositions that make existence claims concerning mathematical objects, i.e , we would need to explain how mathematical objects exist.

However, in this paper I take a different argumentative path. My main purpose is not to argue for the objectivity of mathematics, nor will I aim to explain the way in which mathematical objects exist. 6 Instead, I will show how we can make sense of the two main reasons for believing in the objectivity of mathematics: the apparent objectivity of mathematics and mathematical applications in the sciences. Ultimately, I will argue that whether one accepts mathematics as being objective or not, there is a better argument for the putative objectivity of mathematical discourse than either platonism or nativism. Thus, even though I will not be arguing for the objectivity of mathematics per se , I consider its apparent objectivity to be a strong reason for considering the possibility that mathematics, and mathematical knowledge, are objective. 7

First, however, we need to establish criteria for objectivity in order to determine whether the apparent objectivity of mathematical discourse is of the type that we would generally accept as being objective. Shapiro [2007] has used Wright’s [ 1992 ] influential criteria for the objectivity of discourse for a similar purpose, arguing that mathematical discourse is indeed objective. The three criteria are epistemic constraint , cognitive command , and wider cosmological role . 8 The criterion of epistemic constraint states that non-objective matters are always knowable, i.e. , for non-objective matters it is always the case that:

|$P\leftrightarrow (P$| may be known). [ Wright, 1992 , p. 75].

While this touches upon some of the most fundamental questions in philosophy of mathematics ( e.g. , the question of provability vs truth; see [ Pantsar, 2009 ] for more), I take it is as uncontroversial that mathematical truths can at least appear to be unknowable. For one thing, there are well-defined mathematical problems that are generally considered to be too complex computationally to be solved for large enough inputs [ Arora and Barak, 2007 ; Pantsar, 2019b ; 2021a ]. There is also the Gödelian [ 1931 ] restriction that no consistent formal system strong enough to express arithmetic can be complete, i.e. , prove all true sentences in the system. If we accept that proof from axioms is our way of knowing things in mathematics, this alone implies that there are unknowable truths in our mathematical systems. 9 But even disregarding such limitations of formal axiomatic systems, it is clear that formal (as well as informal) mathematical languages can be complex enough to make the prospect of knowing every truth expressible in them unfeasible. This is enough to accept that mathematical knowledge at least appears to be such that it does not meet the epistemic constraint, which suffices for the present purposes.

Wright’s [ 1992 , p. 92] criterion of cognitive command means that a discourse concerns something objective if and only if we can a priori rule out the possibility that there are disagreements that Shapiro [ 2007 , p. 356] calls ‘blameless’. In a blameless disagreement, there is no reason such as divergent information or different conditions for explaining the disagreement. Roughly put, blameless disagreements are seen as differences in opinion that cannot be solved, akin to matters of taste. A case could be made that in mathematics there appear to be just such disagreements. Should we accept the continuum hypothesis? The axiom of choice? The parallel axiom? In different times, different mathematicians have held different views on them and many other mathematical statements. It could be argued that whether we include the axiom of choice in the axioms of set theory, for example, gives us two different systems of mathematics, neither of which is more correct than the other. In other words, a blameless disagreement is reached and hence in such cases it would appear that the criterion of cognitive command fails. Here I cannot analyze that question in detail (see [ Tait, 2001 ] and [ Shapiro, 2007 ] for interesting treatments), but as far as apparent objectivity is concerned, it seems clear that at least much of mathematics fulfills the criterion of cognitive command. There is no (blameless) disagreement over, for example, what should be acceptable theorems in basic arithmetic. If, like Dostoevsky’s character in Notes from Underground [ 1864 ], somebody claims that |$2 + 2 = 5$|⁠ , it would standardly not be considered to be grounds for a blameless disagreement.

Finally, the criterion of wider cosmological role demands that in order to concern something objective, a discourse must feature also in explanations that are not exclusive to that discourse [ Wright, 1992 , p. 198]. This criterion would seem to be straightforwardly met by mathematical discourse due to the rich variety of applications it has in science. However, as we will see in the next section, the matter is not quite that simple. It could be that the mathematical applications are dispensable from the scientific explanations, in which case the wider cosmological role of mathematical discourse could be put into question. Yet it can hardly be contested that mathematics at least appears to play an explanatory role in sciences. For the present purposes, that is enough. We can safely conclude that the appearance of mathematical objectivity is indeed of the kind of objectivity that Wright [1992] has in mind.

As stated in the introduction, I see two main reasons for believing in the objectivity of mathematical knowledge. First is that mathematical knowledge appears to be objective. Second is that mathematical knowledge is intertwined in a significant way with scientific knowledge that is generally accepted to be objective. While the latter is a much-discussed philosophical argument, which I will explore in more detail below, the first reason may initially seem feeble, since appearances can be misleading in philosophy. Shapiro [1997] , for example, has written about working realism , the way in which most mathematicians work as if mathematical objects were real. Mathematical language is full of existential expressions with apparent commitment to objects. But for a working realist, writing that ‘there exists a number’ may not entail any metaphysical commitment to the existence of numbers. It might be simply a convenient way of expressing something metaphysically far more economical, like ‘from generally agreed upon axioms, with generally accepted rules of proof we can deduce that ...’.

Nevertheless, I contend that the apparent objectivity of mathematical knowledge demands an explanation. The first question to ask, however, is how pervasive a phenomenon is the apparent objectivity? There are regrettably few studies on the topic and, to the best of my knowledge, there are none that reliably and systematically explore views on mathematical objectivity. 10 However, based on the data presented by Müller-Hill [2009] , we can proceed under the assumption that at least for a significant portion of mathematicians (as well as non-mathematicians), mathematical knowledge appears to be objective. In any case, in the present context it is important to distinguish the question whether mathematical knowledge is objective from the question why mathematical knowledge appears to be objective. With this distinction in place, we arrive at three philosophically interesting positions. First is that mathematical knowledge appears to be objective because it is objective in essentially the way it appears on a literal reading. In short, mathematical statements are true because they state facts about mind-independent objects and relations between them. I take this to be a common position among platonists, although the apparent objectivity could be independent of the actual objectivity. 11 The second position is that the apparent objectivity is indeed due to actual objectivity, but it comes from other sources, and not mind-independent mathematical objects. I take cognitive nativism to adhere to this view. The third view is that mathematical knowledge appears to be objective even though it is in fact not objective.

The first two positions will be analyzed in detail in the rest of this paper, but let us first focus on the third option. This last position implies that mathematical knowledge is ultimately about human conventions and nothing else. I call this view strict conventionalism , to distinguish it from more moderate positions that take conventions to play an important part in mathematical discourse. 12 For strict conventionalists, mathematics is about arbitrary rules of symbol manipulation and it cannot be tied to anything more robust. This is the view of at least Field [1980] and Balaguer [2009] , and it is commonly attributed also to Wittgenstein [1976] . 13 Furthermore, this is also the view often associated with mathematical formalism , although this issue is trickier due to the different meanings of formalism in the philosophy of mathematics (see, e.g. , [ Linnebo, 2017 ]). But combining conventionalism and formalism, mathematics could be likened to a game like chess in that it is about clearly defined, well-established rules, and these rules are human inventions.

However, as one of the pioneers of formalism (but certainly not conventionalism), Frege already noted in his Grundgesetze , there is a very important difference between chess and mathematics. Unlike the rules of chess, the rules of mathematics have important applications outside their own domain [ Frege, 1893/1903 ]. This brings us to the second main reason why mathematical knowledge is considered to be objective. Aside from its apparent objectivity, mathematical knowledge has widespread applications in science, and there are few philosophers who are ready to question the objectivity (at least as an ideal) of scientific knowledge. 14 In contemporary philosophy of mathematics, applications have become the main argument for the objectivity of mathematical knowledge [ Colyvan, 2001 ; Brown, 2008 ; Lange, 2017 ]. How could mathematics be an arbitrary game when it is integral to modern science which can explain all kinds of non-mathematical matters? This argument carries significant power for philosophers with radically different views. Field [1980] , for example, considers it the strongest argument for mathematical realism (which he argues against).

The topic of scientific applications of mathematics is particularly important because it moves the focus from the appearance of objectivity to something more substantial. After all, the appearance of objectivity could be simply due to firmly established customs. We know that how the queen moves in chess is a matter of convention, but we might be unable to detect more fundamental and general rules as conventions. Indeed, mathematical rules can be such deeply entrenched conventions. That multiplying two negative numbers produces a positive number, for example, is a mathematical convention that is difficult to see as anything other than convention. There are good algebraic reasons for this custom, but what could be the non-conventional understanding of a negative times a negative quantity? However, does |$(-4)*(-4)=16$| appear any less objective than |$4*4=16$| to most people with basic mathematics education? 15 And if a convention like that appears to be objective, could it be that all of mathematics is actually similar?

However, even if strict conventionalists could explain the apparent objectivity of mathematics, mathematical applications in science provide a much more difficult challenge. Conventionalists are of course aware of this problem. Indeed, applications outside mathematics are often evoked as the only reason why we prefer some mathematical theories over others. Field [ 1980 , p. 15], for example, has argued that we prefer mathematical theories over their alternatives not because they are true, but because they are more useful . Since mathematical theories are not about anything objective, no theory is truer than its alternatives. They can only be more useful. However, this is a problematic state of affairs, even if we bought into Field’s [ 1980 ] claim that mathematics can be taken out of scientific theories without losing any non-mathematical explanatory power, i.e. , mathematics is not indispensable for scientific explanations. 16 An inevitable follow-up question is why certain mathematical theories are more useful than others. Field’s theory seems to imply that this is an arbitrary matter, but if we can find reasons to believe that the matter is not arbitrary, clearly the alternative explanation would be preferable.

Volumes have been written about mathematical explanations in science and it is not possible to go into the full range of details of the topic here (for overviews, see [ Colyvan, 2001 ; Lange, 2017 ; Pincock, 2012 ; Reutlinger and Saatsi, 2018 ; Pantsar, 2018b ]). I will only mention one much-discussed example that will make it sufficiently clear what the problem is. Baker [2005 ; 2009] brought to the attention of philosophers a phenomenon from biology [ Yoshimura, 1997 ], in which species of cicadas have life cycles that include nymphal stages of either 13 or 17 years, depending on the geographic area. The long nymphal stage by itself poses an interesting question, but particularly intriguing is why 13 or 17, but not 15 or 16 years? The only proposed explanation so far that makes sense appeals to the arithmetical fact that 13 and 17 are prime numbers whereas 15 and 16 are not. Prime number nymphal periods mean fewer intersections with the periods of other insects with multi-year nymphal stages, giving the cicadas an evolutionary advantage.

This explanation of the prime nymphal periods is clearly partly biological (concerning, e.g. , the life cycles of the cicadas), but prime numbers seem to play a crucial role in the explanation. However, it is a highly debated matter whether prime numbers are indispensable for the explanation, making the explanation ‘genuinely mathematical’. 17 In the conventionalist position of Field, no mathematical explanation of a non-mathematical phenomenon is indispensable, but we choose some theories because they are useful in explanations. Yet it is difficult to see how the move from indispensability to usefulness changes the fundamental problem. Rather than asking why a mathematical theory is indispensable, we should now ask why a mathematical theory is useful. As I see it, the issue itself remains equally important, and the strict conventionalist can only propose that the matter is arbitrary. Thus the strict conventionalist position has a serious weakness. It cannot (nor does it aim to) provide a feasible non-arbitrary explanation why some mathematical theories have knowledge-inducing applications and others do not. For this reason, I will move the focus in the next two sections to two alternative explanations of the usefulness of mathematics, namely platonism and cognitive nativism, before developing my own view in Section 6.

Linnebo [2018b] defines mathematical platonism as the conjunction of three claims. Existence states that there are mathematical objects, abstractness that the objects are abstract, and independence that mathematical objects are independent of our languages, thoughts, and practices. Following this definition, any epistemological theory associated with platonism must take mathematical knowledge to be objective. As initial presuppositions of platonist epistemology, I take it as uncontroversial that expressions used in mathematical theorems refer to mathematical objects, and that knowledge of mathematical theorems requires the theorems to be true . In platonist philosophy, the class of true mathematical statements is determined by the characteristics of mathematical objects which, due to the independence claim, do not depend on our particular mathematical languages, thoughts, and practices. Consequently, Wright’s [ 1992 ] criteria of epistemic constraint and cognitive command would seem to be immediately met. 18

Platonism about mathematics, as understood above, is not a uniform view, but a heterogeneous collection of various epistemological and metaphysical positions. The common thread to platonism is that it endorses realism about mathematical statements or objects, but this can mean radically different things. Traditionally, platonism referred to the view that mathematical objects have a mind-independent existence. However, modern platonists, like Shapiro [1997 ; 2000] , are more likely to argue that it is about mathematical structures rather than objects like numbers. Also epistemologically, hard-line positions like Gödel’s [ 1983 ] ‘special epistemic faculty’ are rare in modern platonism. Not to attack a straw man, here I focus on the type of platonism that aims to minimize epistemological and ontological commitments. In particular, I will restrict my analysis to the diverse arguments according to which mathematical objects do have a mind-independent existence, but it is a ‘thin’ existence as a referent of true statements, and nothing more.

As Linnebo [ 2018a , p. 4] has put it, ‘thin objects’ are such that their existence ‘does not make a substantial demand of the world’. More precisely, in Linnebo’s [ 2018a ] account the notion of thin objects is understood in the Fregean, maximally general, sense, as referents of singular terms. Frege’s [ 1884 ] famous definition of number was based on the following abstraction principle :

The number of |$F$| s is equal to the number of |$G$| s if and only if |$F$| s are equinumerous with |$G$| s.

The neo-Fregean position of Hale and Wright [2001 ; 2009] , among others, is based on the same idea: the only role played by numbers is as referents of singular terms, i.e. , for ‘the number of |$F$| s is equal to the number of |$G$| s’ to be true it only needs to be the case that |$F$| s are equinumerous with |$G$| s. 19 This is the fundamental idea behind referring to objects in terms of abstraction principles. They give a criterion of identity for new concepts by ‘carving up’ previous propositional content. Frege’s [ 1884 ] famous example was the abstraction principle:

The direction of line |$A$| is the same as the direction of line |$B$| if and only if |$A$| and |$B$| are parallel.

By carving up the propositional content of two lines being parallel, new abstract objects (directions) are introduced. This is what Linnebo [2018a] means by thin objects: numbers and directions are referents of singular terms in the abstraction principles, and that is all they are required to be. Thus, while numbers and directions are abstract objects as referents of singular terms, their existence does not make any substantial demands of the world. 20

In the introduction, I mentioned the epistemological problem of Benacerraf [1973] as perhaps the main difficulty that a platonist account in the philosophy of mathematics faces. For the platonists, as Benacerraf saw it, the epistemological problem was in explaining a connection between humans as physical subjects and causally inert abstract mathematical objects. Both Linnebo and the neo-Fregeans aim to escape this problem by arguing that the thin notion of mathematical objects does not require any epistemological connection that is not present in the abstraction principles. Since the accounts involving thin objects do not require ontology beyond the abstraction principles, they also avoid Benacerraf’s epistemological problem.

However, those accounts are now faced with the problem of explaining what the existence of thin objects amounts to. Most importantly, one can ask whether the thin objects exist in the mind-independent manner required of platonism under Linnebo’s definition. Rayo [2013 ; 2015] has argued for a theory he calls ‘subtle platonism’ as a way of escaping the problem. The fundamental idea of this subtle reading of platonism is that mathematical objects like numbers exist, but they do so in a trivial sense. Essentially this refers to the triviality of the compositional semantics for mathematical statements. Standard semantics would imply that an arithmetical statement like ‘ |$1 + 1 = 2$| ’ can only be true if the world contains numbers. If the world does not contain numbers, as Field [1980] , for example, has argued, any existential mathematical statement ( ⁠|$1 + 1 = 2$| can be formulated as one) is always false. After all, for a mathematical statement to be true, under this conception, there have to exist mathematical objects. One popular solution to this problem is that existential mathematical statements should be paraphrased in nominalistic or modal terms ( e.g. , [ Putnam, 1967 ; Chihara, 1973 ; 1990 ; 2005 ; Hellman, 1989 ; 1905 ]). In this approach, phrases like ‘there exists x ’ are replaced by phrases like ‘it is possible to construct x ’ [ Chihara, 2005 ]. Shapiro [ 1997 , p. 228] has argued against such paraphrasing strategies by pointing out the infeasibility of solving ontological problems by a mere change of vocabulary. More recently, also Rayo [2015] has argued that the different ways of paraphrasing mathematical statements to avoid existential quantification do not solve the problem. However, he contends that his trivial semantics does, because in it the truth conditions for mathematical statements do not require substantial existence claims; hence the characterization of them as trivial. Let us take a closer look at what this means. Rayo [2013 ; 2015] does not aim to avoid commitment to numbers. Rather, he accepts that arithmetical statements commit to numbers, but for the statements to be true, there is no need for numbers to exist in a non-trivial manner. Consider his example: ‘the number of dinosaurs is zero’. According to Rayo, for this sentence to be true it is only required that there are no dinosaurs, i.e. , the sentence is true in a possible world w if and only if there are no dinosaurs in w . The truth condition (the right-hand side of the biconditional) says nothing about numbers. As he formulates it:

For the number of the dinosaurs to be zero just is for there to be no dinosaurs. [ Rayo, 2015 , p. 81; emphasis original]

Hence, Rayo points out, there is no difference between there being no dinosaurs and the number of dinosaurs being zero. Generally:

‘For the number of the F s to be n   just is for it to be the case that |$\exists!_{n}x(Fx)$| ’ ( ibid ., emphasis original). 21

In other words, there is no difference between there being |$n$| things that have the property F and the number of F s being n . Moving to purely arithmetical sentences like ‘ |$1+ 1 = 2$| ’, Rayo argues, the truth conditions are satisfied trivially regardless of what the world is like, since the right-hand side of the biconditional

|$1 + 1 = 2$| is true if and only if |$1 + 1 = 2$|

is fulfilled in all possible worlds. Thus, arithmetical sentences commit to numbers, yet by trivial semantics they escape Benacerraf’s problem. After all, Rayo [2015] argues, the commitment to numbers does not have anything to do with the truth conditions of arithmetical sentences; so there is no epistemological cost.

Rayo’s subtle platonism shows promise in offering an epistemologically feasible platonist alternative to conventionalism, since it does what platonists generally aim to do: instead of advocating a paraphrasing or revisionist alteration of mathematics, it takes mathematical practice as it is and maintains that commitment to numbers need not carry any epistemological problems. Yet it is not clear that this commitment to numbers amounts to anything more than applying a particular use of language. For all there is to its credit, Rayo’s account appears to take such a general way of understanding the commitment to numbers that it is questionable whether it can be called platonism, even as a subtle variant. It is possible to entertain an alternative view, according to which the only commitment being made is to a linguistic practice, which may not be anything more than a conventional shorthand. And if this is the case, Rayo’s subtle platonism will end up with the same potential problem of arbitrariness as the conventionalist accounts.

One might wonder how this could be the case since the truth conditions of arithmetical statements are clearly not arbitrary. The number of dinosaurs is zero just in case there are no dinosaurs. But there being no dinosaurs is not something arbitrary, it is a fact concerning dinosaurs. That the number of Earth’s moons is one is not arbitrary, and so on. This is clear enough, but what is there to prevent statements of pure arithmetic like |$1 + 1 = 2$| from being arbitrary? Rayo [2015] discusses also pure arithmetic in terms of triviality: the truth conditions of |$1 + 1 = 2$| are trivial because they are satisfied regardless of what the world is like, and hence the existence of numbers is also trivial. In this picture, there is no room for non-trivial truth-makers for arithmetical statements. Yet I can envision a possible world where the truth conditions of |$1 + 1 = 2$| are not trivial: a world with no subjects who process their observations, thoughts, or ideas in terms of numbers. In such a world the truth condition of |$1 + 1 = 2$| would not be trivial, since any proposition involving natural numbers would require new conceptual thinking. This is not to say that |$1 + 1 = 2$| would be false (or without truth value) in such possible worlds. Rather, the argument is that in such possible worlds there would be no cognitive agents who possess number concepts. Consequently, the truth conditions of |$1 + 1 = 2$| are not satisfied regardless of what the world is like. For them to be satisfied, there need to be cognitive agents who possess number concepts, or at least some form of equivalent numerical ability. 22

Neither would it be trivial that the number of Earth’s moons is one, because it would not be trivial that things are discussed in terms of their number. Understanding such statements and establishing their truth would require the subjects first to learn about natural numbers, or at least a small finite subset of them. This brings us to what I see as the real crux of the matter: just how do we initially learn about natural numbers and the way they can be associated with objects in the world? Rayo’s account does not get involved with this issue. In the context I have brought up, however, what appears to be trivial may not be so trivial after all. And if we can identify non-trivial truth-makers for arithmetical statements, we must reconsider how Rayo’s account should be interpreted — including the triviality of the existence of numbers.

In a similar way, I see a potential problem with the thin objects of Linnebo and the neo-Fregean account of abstract objects. Abstraction principles may indeed carve out the propositional content so that reference to new abstract objects is possible, and manage to do that in an epistemologically unproblematic way. But why do we end up endorsing particular abstraction principles like Hume’s principle? Is it really the case that we have an understanding of the principle of equinumerosity which we then use to introduce the concept of number? Or did the concept of number exist beforehand, and equinumerosity is used to characterize it? This is at least a plausible possibility, given how numbers have been referred to for millennia without explicit recourse to abstraction principles like Hume’s principle. Now the question is, could it be the case that there has been reference to numbers even without implicit use of equinumerosity? Could there be reference to numbers due to some other kind of epistemological access besides abstraction principles? If so, would this reference still make numbers ‘thin’ objects in the sense of Linnebo’s account?

In the next two sections, I will discuss that possibility and its philosophical consequences in detail. For now, however, let us assume that the account of thin objects is correct for mathematical objects. Can this account escape the conventionalist threat mentioned above in reference to the trivial truth conditions of Rayo’s account? If mathematical objects only exist as referents of abstraction principles, is there any reason to believe that mathematical knowledge concerns anything more than conventions? If not, is there any reason still to believe that mathematical knowledge is objective ? Returning to Wright’s [ 1992 ] criteria of objectivity, it is not clear that any of them are necessarily met by the accounts of Linnebo and Rayo, which makes it necessary to reassess how platonist those views are. Epistemic constraint seems questionable, given that the abstraction principles may be just conventions; a further argument would be needed to establish that they are more than that. Similarly, the criterion of cognitive command may not be met if we do not have any non-conventional reasons to choose some abstraction principles over others.

However, the most serious problem concerns the criterion of wider cosmological role. How can we justify that mathematical discourse, as envisioned in the accounts of Linnebo and Rayo, is used outside mathematics? If the abstraction principles or the trivial mathematical truths are only conventions, I cannot see any such justification. The accounts would run into the most serious problem of conventionalism as discussed in the previous section: mathematical applications in science appear to be arbitrary. If the abstraction principles are based on something more than conventions, however, we can no longer assume — at least without argument — that mathematical objects only have a thin or trivial existence. In other words, the epistemologically unproblematic versions of platonism proposed by Linnebo and Rayo face a new challenge: they must explain why they should still be associated with platonism, instead of conventionalism. For Linnebo [2018b] , platonist mathematical objects are abstract, and they exist in a manner independent of thought, language, and practice. In order for the account of Linnebo to remain platonist, since the propositional content in the abstraction principles is responsible for the existence of mathematical objects, it must be independent of our thoughts, languages, and practices.

As I will argue in the concluding section, there is indeed a non-conventionalist way of understanding thin objects. But before we can establish that, we should know just how mathematical thoughts, languages, and practices come to exist. I will propose an explanation in Section 6. For now, however, let us return briefly to traditional forms of platonism, according to which mathematical objects have an existence that is not thin. Clearly they fulfill Wright’s criteria of epistemic constraint and cognitive command for objectivity. But are they in a better position to explain the wider cosmological role of mathematics, namely the existence of mathematical applications in science? The best-known answer is provided by Quine [1966 ; 1969] , according to whom we cannot separate the mathematical content from the non-mathematical content in scientific theories, and therefore both should have the same ontological status. 23 If we accept, for example, that prime numbers are indispensable for the best explanation of the cicada nymphal stages, we must accept that prime numbers are as real as the insects or the molecules they consist of. In this holistic picture of scientific explanations, we cannot cherry-pick the objects that we make ontological commitment to.

Yet it seems clear that abstract mathematical objects must be in some way very different from physical objects. In this respect, the Quinean account does not provide us with many answers. Even if we agreed that there should be ontological commitment to mathematical objects, just as there is to non-mathematical objects, we are still left with the question how abstract and non-abstract objects are connected in scientific explanations. I see this as a basic problem of platonism about mathematics with regard to scientific explanations. Granted, Quine’s argument gives uniformity to the explanations in terms of ontological commitments: physical objects have a mind-independent existence and so do mathematical ones. But this alone does little to explain the wider cosmological role of mathematics. For that, there would need to be an explanation of how abstract mathematical objects (or structures) and physical objects are related to each other. While such accounts have been discussed (see, e.g. , [ Brown, 2008 ]), none of them seems to bridge the gap between the abstract and the physical in a satisfactory way. Unfortunately, analyzing them goes beyond the scope of this paper. Instead, I will move on to a different type of account of mathematical knowledge and see how they fare with the questions of objectivity and applications. If successful, such accounts can potentially solve the problem of integrating abstract and non-abstract objects in scientific theories.

As we saw in the previous section, platonist approaches have developed into increasingly light ontological and epistemological variations, up to the point that it becomes necessary to ask what distinguishes them from conventionalist positions about mathematical knowledge. But in one way these new variations of platonism, such as those of Rayo [2015] and Linnebo [2018a] , but also others like Peacocke [1993] , Shapiro [1997] , and Brown [2008] , are very much part of the older platonist tradition: their methodology takes epistemology and ontology of mathematics to be an a priori pursuit in which we can elucidate the nature of mathematical knowledge through logical and conceptual analysis.

As was mentioned in the introduction, however, recently this approach has been challenged by researchers who believe that we can explain mathematical knowledge on the basis of the evolutionarily determined ability to treat quantitative information that we already possess as infants and share with many non-human animals ( e.g. , [ Dehaene, 1997/2011 ; Butterworth, 1999 ; Lakoff and Núñez, 2000 ; Carey, 2009 ]). On this view, the a priori approach to philosophy of mathematics is largely replaced by empirical research on our cognitive capacities, which can reveal how mathematical knowledge is possible, and what it is about. 24 An important part of this work is empirical research on young children (often infants) and non-human animals. Numerous authors have concluded that infants and many non-human animals, including primates and parrots, but also fish, have numerical abilities [ Starkey and Cooper, 1980 ; Dehaene, 1997/2011 ; Hauser et al. , 2000 ; Cantlon and Brannon, 2006 ; Pepperberg, 2012 ]. Indeed, many influential authors explicitly call these animal and infant abilities arithmetical ( e.g. , [ Wynn, 1992 ; Dehaene, 2001 ; Rugani et al. , 2009 ; Agrillo, 2015 ]. As mentioned in the introduction, I call this account nativism (or cognitive nativism) about arithmetical knowledge.

Both platonism and nativism would appear to be committed to the position that mathematical — or at least arithmetical — knowledge is essentially objective. On the nativist account, which takes arithmetical ability to be the product of biological evolution, no existence of mathematical objects needs to be assumed. If it is accepted that the evolutionarily developed arithmetical ability constitutes knowledge and it is (at least partly) shared with infants [ Wynn, 1992 ] and newly hatched chicks [ Rugani et al. , 2009 ], there would seem to be a strong case for its objectivity. Rather than being in some essential way dependent on the content of our thoughts, languages, or conventions, arithmetical knowledge would be determined by evolutionary processes that have led to biological characteristics we possess already as infants and share with a wide range of non-human animals.

This way, platonism and nativism both have a straightforward explanation for the apparent objectivity of mathematical knowledge. But given that in nativism no mathematical objects are presumed to exist, with an Occam-type parsimony principle, this appears to give the nativist position an edge over at least the traditional ‘non-thin’ versions of platonism: it does not have to face Benacerraf’s epistemological challenge, as it does not require the existence of mind-independent abstract objects. 25 Neither does nativism succumb to the arbitrariness of mathematics that threatens conventionalist theories. The class of sentences considered to be mathematical truths would not be arbitrary, since it would be (at least partly) determined by biological characteristics due to evolutionary processes.

However, as I have argued elsewhere in detail [ Pantsar, 2014 ; 2015a ; 2018a ; 2019a ; 2020 ], the problem with the above line of argumentation is that it assumes that the infant and animal quantitative ability is indeed arithmetical. This is often explicitly claimed. For example, one of the most important and influential researchers in the field, Dehaene, writes:

In the course of biological evolution, selection has shaped our brain representations to ensure that they are adapted to the external world. I have argued that arithmetic is such an adaptation. [ 2001 , p. 31]

That arithmetic is such an evolutionarily determined adaptation is a very problematic assumption and unsupported by empirical evidence. To see this, let us consider the famous infant experiment reported by Wynn [1992] . It had been previously established that infants can distinguish between small numerosities [ Starkey and Cooper, 1980 ]. This ability, called subitizing , generally stops working after three or four objects, but until then it allows determining the number of objects in our field of vision without counting. There are good empirical reasons to believe that we already possess the subitizing ability as infants and share it with many non-human animals (see, e.g. , [ Dehaene, 1997/2011 ; Spelke, 2000 ]). What Wynn argued was that, based on the subitizing ability, infants can in fact carry out simple addition and subtraction operations. She observed infants reacting with surprise ( i.e. , longer looking time) to the ‘unnatural arithmetic’ of |$1 + 1 = 1$|⁠ , instantiated by the infant seeing two dolls being put behind a screen but only one being there after the screen was lifted (the other having been removed clandestinely). From different configurations in the subitizing range (from one to four), she concluded that infants are able to carry out rudimentary arithmetical operations. But as I have argued before [ 2018a ], this conclusion is unwarranted. The infants’ behavior could be explained by their having some kind of cognitive mechanism or procedure in place for keeping track of one small quantity at a time. When the exposed quantity of objects did not match their expectations, they were surprised. Under this explanation, nothing like an arithmetical operation is presupposed to take place in the cognitive process. What is presupposed is merely an ability to track small quantities, which gets wide support from empirical data.

This distinction is crucial to make. We must not confuse developed arithmetical ability with primitive quantitative abilities, nor assume that the difference is only gradual. In my previous work, I have distinguished between proto-arithmetical quantitative ability and actual arithmetical ability for exactly this purpose [ 2014 ; 2018a ; 2019a ]. 26 It could be that the subitizing ability and the object-tracking system that makes it possible form the cognitive foundation for the development of arithmetical ability ([ Carey, 2009 ; Beck, 2017 ]; see also [ Pantsar, 2021b ]). At least a partial cognitive foundation for arithmetic could also be found in another evolutionarily developed quantitative ability, the estimation ability due to the approximate number system that we also possess as infants and share with non-human animals [ Dehaene, 1997/2011 ]. 27 But even if this were the case, the proto-arithmetical ability, or abilities, need to be treated as conceptually distinct from arithmetical ability. The proto-arithmetical subitizing and estimation abilities may be related to arithmetical knowledge, but to what extent and how is something that needs to be carefully analyzed. What the infants are doing in Wynn’s experiment may be described with the help of arithmetical language (such as |$1+1=2$|⁠ ). But this must not be confused with the infants’ actually carrying out addition (or subtraction) operations, even in rudimentary forms. Therefore, I am ready to accept the above quotation of Dehaene only after one crucial amendment. I agree with the plausibility of the general principle that ‘In the course of biological evolution, selection has shaped our brain representations to ensure that they are adapted to the external world’. However, rather than arithmetic, it is the proto-arithmetical ability (or abilities) that are such an adaptation.

With the focus moved to proto-mathematical abilities, the question becomes whether the nativist account can still account for the apparent objectivity of mathematical knowledge, as well as mathematical applications. There are arguments both for and against the apparent objectivity. Support for the apparent objectivity comes from history. Unlike many other crucial innovations, like the alphabet, which is generally thought to have developed only once during known human history (see, e.g. , [ Sampson, 1985 ]), arithmetic is known to have developed several times independently [ Ifrah, 1998 ]. The particular systems of arithmetic have had different characteristics but they have also shown great similarity both in terms of counting and operations (addition and multiplication). This suggests that the development of arithmetic taps into the proto-arithmetical abilities, which determine in an important way the content of arithmetical theories. Indeed, most known languages have some kind of a numeral system, and many of these systems show recursivity in some numeral base [ Ifrah, 1998 ]. If the proto-arithmetical abilities are the reason for this kind of independent development of numeral systems and arithmetical knowledge in different cultures, there is a strong case to be made that arithmetical knowledge is objective in a relevant sense. At the very least, it would appear to be objective.

However, there are also human cultures, such as the Amazonian tribes of Pirahã and Munduruku, whose knowledge and skills with quantities are not considerably above the primitive quantitative systems shared with many non-human animals [ Gordon, 2004 ; Pica et al. , 2004 ]. The Pirahã numeral system, for example, includes words roughly for ‘one’, ‘two’, and ‘many’, which are not used in a consistent manner. Yet both the Pirahã and the Munduruku have the same (or similar) proto-arithmetical subitizing and estimation abilities as we do [ Gordon, 2004 ; Pica et al. , 2004 ; Dehaene et al. , 2008 ]. This tells us that having proto-arithmetical abilities is not sufficient for developing even rudimentary numeral systems, let alone proper arithmetic. There appears to be a connection between the proto-arithmetical abilities and arithmetic, but clearly the former underdetermine the development of the latter.

The upshot of this is that we cannot directly establish proto-arithmetical abilities as the foundation of arithmetic, which in turn implies that arithmetical knowledge could be in an important way dependent on human conventions. This possibility would be highly problematic for the nativist position, since it could be the case that arithmetical knowledge is in fact to a large extent independent of the proto-arithmetical abilities. After all, with the distinction between proto-arithmetical and arithmetical abilities in place, it becomes clear that it is nativism over the proto-arithmetical abilities that the empirical evidence supports. While the apparent objectivity of proto-arithmetical abilities would not be in question, the apparent objectivity of arithmetical (and presumably other mathematical) knowledge could not be exclusively, or even mainly, due to the evolutionarily developed abilities that are the foundation of the nativist position.

The role of mathematics in the sciences would suffer the same destiny in that scenario: if mathematics is not fundamentally a product of the evolutionarily developed proto-arithmetic, and possibly other proto-mathematical abilities, the success of mathematical applications in science could be either a coincidence or based on the conventionalist character of both mathematics and science. No more substantial link between the two could be drawn.

However, I do not believe that to be the case. There is no reason to believe that infants and non-human animals have arithmetical (or other mathematical) abilities, but as I will argue in the next section, there are very good reasons to think that the proto-arithmetical (and possible other proto-mathematical) abilities form a partial cognitive foundation for arithmetic (and other areas of mathematics). Arithmetic has developed in different cultures, e.g. , the Chinese, Mayans, and Greek, independently in ways that converge in terms of counting and basic operations like addition and multiplication [ Ifrah, 1998 ]. However, in terms of numeral systems, arithmetical practices and applications, the different cultures show also a great deal of divergence [ Ifrah, 1998 ; Pantsar, 2019a ]. Thus I will argue in the next section that cultural factors play an integral role in the development of arithmetic, making it underdetermined by the proto-arithmetical abilities. Hence the nativist position is not plausible in the face of the best data and theoretical understanding we have about arithmetical and proto-arithmetical cognition. But with a proper understanding of the development of arithmetic from its proto-arithmetical origins, we can still trace the cognitive foundations of mathematics at least partly to evolutionarily developed abilities.

In the previous section, I criticized Dehaene [2001] for not distinguishing between proto-arithmetic and arithmetic, and consequently for claiming that arithmetic is an evolutionarily developed adaptation. I believe that this equivocation is much more than a mere terminological issue, and both in empirical research and philosophy there should be an aim to rid the literature of such possible confusions. However, I do not want to claim that Dehaene (or others making a similar equivocation) sees arithmetic as entirely a product of biological evolution. Indeed, Dehaene explicitly recognizes also another type of evolution crucial for the development of mathematics:

Specific to the human species, however, is a second level of evolution at the cultural level. As humans, we are born with multiple intuitions concerning numbers, sets, continuous quantities, iteration, logic, or the geometry of space. Through language and the development of new symbols systems, we have the ability to build extensions of these foundational systems and to draw various links between them. [ Dehaene, 2001 , p. 31]

Again, it is important to be careful with terminology like ‘multiple intuitions’. I would not be prepared say, for example, that we have intuitions about numbers and sets. I do think we have proto-arithmetical abilities that can lead to something that may feasibly be called ‘intuitions’ about numbers. I also believe that it is possible that we have similar proto-geometrical, as well as possibly proto-set-theoretical and proto-logical abilities. But it is important that these be distinguished from any genuinely mathematical intuitions. When it comes to the latter, however, Dehaene points out one crucial aspect. Language and symbol systems allow extending and drawing links between intuitions, although, as we will see, there are also other factors involved. Nevertheless, having made these clarifications, I believe Dehaene is fundamentally correct about the most important aspect. It is indeed the evolution on the cultural level that we need to include in order to explain how the proto-arithmetical abilities can develop into mathematical knowledge and skills.

The variation in quantitative abilities between different cultures is enormous. From research on cultures like Pirahã and Munduruku that appear to have no arithmetical skills and knowledge [ Gordon, 2004 ; Pica et al. , 2004 ] to cultures like the Mayans, ancient Chinese and Greek, which independently made great advances both in arithmetic and its applications, it becomes clear that arithmetic is the product of a long line of development in specific cultural circumstances [ Ifrah, 1998 ]. In the Western tradition heavily developed by the ancient Greek, but following a longer tradition that can be traced at least to Babylon and Egypt, 28 we can see that arithmetic slowly developed into the subject we are currently familiar with. Some important advances have happened quickly due to specific innovations, but in the bigger picture the development of arithmetic has been a long gradual process from the introduction of numerals to modern formal systems [ Boyer, 1991 ]. This is consistent with the theory of cumulative cultural evolution for explaining the development of human knowledge and skills [ Boyd and Richerson, 1985 ; 2005 ; Tomasello, 1999 ; Henrich, 2015 ; Heyes, 2018 ]. According to cumulative cultural evolution, technologies and other cultural innovations are improved upon in small (trans-)generational increments. As these improvements are used widely enough, knowledge and skills based on them can reach a status where they are no longer tied to small groups of individuals. New improvements are adopted widely within cultures and passed on to subsequent generations, enabling a cumulative evolution of culturally developed artifacts, knowledge, and skills. This passage of the knowledge and skills can also extend across cultures through regular interactions.

Basic arithmetic became such a skill in many cultures and arithmetical knowledge was spread increasingly widely. Large groups of children were starting to be educated first in counting processes, then moving on to arithmetical operations. Applications of arithmetic were invented, further strengthening the place of arithmetic within educational and other cultural practices. 29 Ultimately this cultural development made arithmetical knowledge and skills widely possessed, thus facilitating the refinement and development of them, as well as that of the educational practices for distributing them [ Pantsar, 2019a ]. This is the history (and pre-history) behind arithmetic as we currently know it: a subject that the vast majority of children in the world acquire basic knowledge and skills in. 30

Conventionalists might at this point see an argument to support their position. Few culturally developed practices are as widely shared in the modern world as basic arithmetic. If we want to explain the apparent objectivity of arithmetical knowledge, is this widely spread cultural background not enough? If most of the world learns largely similar arithmetical content, is it any wonder that we start seeing arithmetical knowledge as objective? While I believe that the question is well placed, it immediately prompts a further question: why are there such large similarities in basic knowledge and skills when it comes to arithmetic? Is this simply the result of the domination of certain cultures in the modern world, or are there culture-independent factors that determine, at least partly, the similarities in arithmetical knowledge and skills? In order to answer such questions, we need to understand better how cultural learning [ Heyes, 2018 ] takes place, i.e. , how cumulative cultural evolution is possible by transmitting new knowledge and skills to subsequent generations.

In this paper, I apply Menary’s [ 2014 ; 2015 ] notion of enculturation in formulating a theoretical framework for analyzing cultural learning in the field of arithmetic (for more details, see [ Pantsar, 2019a ; 2019b ; 2020 ; 2021b ]. Enculturation refers to transformative processes in which interactions with the surrounding culture determine the way cognitive practices are acquired and developed [ Menary, 2015 ; Fabry, 2018 ]. The fundamental idea behind this framework is that our genetically determined, evolutionarily developed, biological faculties are transformed through the cultural transmission of cognitive practices. The enculturation account is thus a potentially important improvement over crude dichotomies like ‘nature versus nurture’, or as in the present context, conventionalism versus nativism. Instead of focusing on biologically determined abilities or culturally developed abilities separately, the enculturation framework can provide a link between the two. Indeed, in the enculturation framework a strict dichotomy between biology and culture should no longer be made. 31 In the case of arithmetical cognition, researchers have recently seen enculturation as a way to connect research on proto-arithmetical abilities with research on arithmetic as a culturally developed phenomenon [ Menary, 2015 ; Pantsar, 2019a ; Jones, 2020 ; Fabry, 2020 ].

Most researchers of numerical cognition agree that the evolutionarily developed core cognitive quantitative abilities form a cognitive basis for the development of arithmetical abilities. However, as mentioned in the previous section, there is disagreement over which cognitive core system is central in the developmental process. Dehaene [1997/2011] and Halberda and Feigenson [2008] , for example, argue that the approximate number system is the primary core cognitive resource in the development of number concepts and therefore also in the development of arithmetical ability. Many others see the object-tracking system that allows subitizing as the prevalent system in that development ( e.g. , Carey [2009] ; Izard et al. [2008] ; Sarnecka and Carey [2008] ; Carey et al. [2017] ; Beck [2017] ; Cheung and Le Corre [2018] ). There are also researchers, Spelke [2011] , Pantsar [2014 ; 2015a ; 2019a ; 2021b] , vanMarle et al. [2018] , who argue that both core cognitive systems play a crucial role in the process.

While there is still considerable disagreement over the roles that the different cognitive core systems play in the development of arithmetical cognition, with the enculturation framework we can nevertheless propose an explanation of how such development from proto-arithmetical core cognitive abilities to culturally developed arithmetical abilities can take place. The well-established phenomenon of plasticity of the brain is fundamental to the enculturation framework. Through the mechanism Menary [2014] calls learning driven plasticity , the neural plasticity of the brain enables the acquisition of new cognitive capacities. The neural plasticity of the brain allows for structural and functional variations based on the experiences of individuals in their ontogeny [ Dehaene, 2009 ; Ansari, 2008 ; Anderson, 2015 ]. This enables the acquisition of new cognitive abilities such as reading and writing by redeploying older, evolutionarily developed neural circuits for new, culturally specific functions [ Dehaene, 2009 ; Menary, 2014 ]. 32 When it comes to arithmetical cognition, the hypothesis many researchers accept is that the evolutionarily developed proto-arithmetical ability for processing numerosities in the intraparietal sulci, together with linguistic abilities for number words and symbols, is deployed resulting in two different (although partially overlapping) systems for processing numerosities in the brain, thus explaining how adult subjects have both arithmetical and proto-arithmetical abilities [ Dehaene and Cohen, 2007 ; Nieder and Dehaene, 2009 ; Dehaene, 1997/2011 ; Menary, 2015 ].

The enculturation framework can then provide the link between the proto-arithmetical abilities, which are the product of biological evolution , and the arithmetical ability that is the product of cumulative cultural evolution. 33 By redeploying proto-arithmetical neural circuits for arithmetical abilities, individuals are able to acquire culturally developed cognitive practices. This, in turn, enables them to develop further or modify cognitive practices, which can then be adopted more widely in the culture. Therefore enculturation and cumulative cultural evolution form a feedback loop which explains the acquisition and development of cognitive practices. 34 This is consistent with the arguments of Fabry [2017] , who employs Laland’s [ 2017 ] notion of cognitive innovation to analyze the introduction and acquisition of new cognitive practices. Fabry emphasizes the importance of the interplay between cognitive innovations, enculturation, and cumulative cultural evolution in transforming our cognitive capacities. I find the resulting theoretical framework fruitful for explaining how proto-arithmetical abilities are employed in developing arithmetical knowledge and skills, because it connects the phylogenetic and ontogenetic levels of development. On the level of individual ontogenetic development, the proto-arithmetical neural circuits are (partially) redeployed to acquire new numerical cognitive practices. On the phylogenetic level, contributions by individuals make group-level innovation possible, resulting in cumulative cultural evolution that gives rise to new practices, which are acquired by new generations of individuals in ontogeny through the process of enculturation. 35

Many details of this process are as yet unknown, but I contend that the above account provides a feasible framework for explaining how arithmetical knowledge has developed. It is of course possible that there has been at least some genetic and cultural co-evolution in the development of numerical abilities, and the order of development presented above is not fully accurate. 36 However, from what we know about the proto-arithmetical abilities, they are largely universal and do not show significant cultural variation [ Dehaene, 1997/2011 ]. 37 While there may have been some cultural co-evolution of numerical abilities taking place also during the period of the genetic evolution of proto-arithmetical abilities, this effect appears to have been minor.

Importantly, in contrast to the nativist account described in the previous section, the present account does not take arithmetical knowledge to be essentially a product of biological evolution. The cultural aspects of the development of arithmetic play a crucial role in this enculturated epistemological theory of arithmetic. In contrast to strict conventionalist accounts, however, the cultural aspects do not entirely determine arithmetical content. Through the process of re-deploying proto-arithmetical abilities in acquiring and innovating new cognitive practices, arithmetical knowledge is partly determined by the core cognitive, evolutionarily developed, quantitative systems. Not only do I contend that this is the most feasible epistemological account of arithmetic, but it can also provide the best explanation for the two reasons for believing that arithmetical knowledge is objective. It can explain the apparent objectivity of arithmetical and other mathematical knowledge, and it can explain arithmetical and other mathematical applications in science.

On the present epistemological account, there can be two reasons for the apparent objectivity of mathematical knowledge. First, it could be that mathematical knowledge appears to be objective simply because it is based on deeply-entrenched conventions, as discussed in Section 3. However, unlike in the conventionalist theories, on the present account there is also a second plausible reason. Basic arithmetic, at least, appears to be objective to us because it is based on evolutionarily developed proto-arithmetical abilities. These abilities are universal to human beings, except for cases of developmental dysfunctions or injuries. In [ Pantsar, 2014 ], I have called arithmetical knowledge maximally intersubjective because of this biological foundation. From data on different cultures, it appears that we share the proto-mathematical abilities as widely as we share any cognitive or physical abilities [ Dehaene, 1997/2011 ]. They are not dependent on our languages or practices. If arithmetical knowledge and skills are in an important way determined by proto-arithmetical abilities, it is quite understandable that many would in fact consider such maximally intersubjective knowledge to be objective.

I believe that also the wide applicability of mathematics in science can be explained with the present enculturated account of arithmetical and other mathematical knowledge. There are two potential explanations for this, the first of which has been suggested by Bloom [2000] and Maddy [2014] in a slightly different context. Maddy argues that the foundations of arithmetic are a combination of set theory and logic. In particular, logic on her account is based on our evolutionarily developed cognitive abilities. In contrast to the present account, Maddy’s account of arithmetic is thus based on proto-logic rather than proto-arithmetic. I cannot enter the debate between the two positions here (see [ Pantsar, 2016 ] for more), but for the question of applications, Maddy’s explanation is also applicable to my account. She argues that the proto-logical ability has evolutionarily developed to mirror how the world is structured:

Much as our primitive cognitive architecture, designed to detect [the logical structure of the world], produces our firm conviction in simple cases of rudimentary logic, our human language-learning device produces a comparably unwavering confidence in this potentially infinite pattern. [ Maddy, 2014 , p. 234]

In a similar manner, it could be argued that our primitive cognitive architecture is ‘designed’ to detect the arithmetical structure of the world as discrete objects. 38 One argument of that type has been proposed by De Cruz [2016] , who argues that anti-realist accounts fail to explain how the proto-arithmetical ability has evolved. In particular, she asks what the adaptive behavior central to the development of proto-arithmetical ability is based on, if not some type of realist ontology of mathematics. This would then provide a seemingly straightforward explanation for the existence of arithmetical and other mathematical applications in science. If arithmetic, and by extension other fields of mathematics, are based on our evolutionarily developed ability to detect the structure of the world, there is hardly any mystery to the fact that mathematics has applications in explaining that world.

The second explanation for mathematical applications in the present account puts a Kantian twist into the above views of Maddy and De Cruz. Rather than presume that proto-logic or proto-arithmetic detect objective features of the world an sich , it is possible to take the weaker position that they detect the structure our cognitive architecture imposes on our observations and thoughts. Perhaps this also mirrors the structure of the world, but we may never be able to establish that. If all our observations and thoughts are structured by our cognitive architecture, we cannot hope to access the world beyond that structure. This is another debate that I cannot enter here (see [ Pantsar, 2014 ] for more), but this latter ‘Kantian’ account would appear to provide an equally good explanation for the existence of mathematical explanations as the realist accounts of Maddy and De Cruz. To answer De Cruz’s question above, it could be that the evolutionary endowments are simply vindicated by their adaptative success. Observing the world in terms of countable macro-level entities (such as objects and other animals) has clear advantages in acquiring food, avoiding predators, raising offspring, and many other crucial behaviors. However, I do not see why this would imply a realist ontology of numbers either as objects or placeholders in a structure.

It is of course possible that through neural plasticity we develop numerical or logical abilities that do not detect the structure of the world but neither do they detect some inevitable conditions that our cognitive architecture imposes on our observations and thoughts. However, it is at least a plausible hypothesis that the proto-arithmetical abilities are evolutionarily developed in tandem with observing the world in terms of discrete macro-level objects, being thus tied to the general way we experience our surroundings. But it is not my purpose here to argue that this is indeed the case. Instead, I have wanted to establish that the resulting argument is similar both in the scenario in which we assume that the proto-mathematical abilities detect the structure of the world and the scenario in which we believe them to detect inevitable conditions of our observations. If mathematics is in an important way determined by proto-mathematical abilities, mathematics is connected to science through a great variety of crucial applications because (at least part of) mathematics deals with the very foundational structures that science is also based on. In the spirit of Occam, we may want to restrain from making the realist assumption of Maddy or De Cruz, and be content that the relevant foundational structures concern our observational and cognitive capacities. But this does not make mathematical applications in science more problematic in any way, since the connection between mathematics and science is established in a similar manner.

Of course behind these considerations lies the question whether our proto-mathematical abilities are evolved in a ‘truth-tracking’ manner so as to ensure that our cognitive capacities provide us with accurate information about the structure of world. There are ways in which such truth tracking seems plausible. Subitizing and estimating can give animals important information that can help with survival and success in life. Being able to establish the numerosity of prey animals or predators, for example, can be the difference between thriving and perishing. Not being able to track the quantity of offspring can be disadvantageous to protecting them and thus prevent the offspring from reaching maturity.

It should also be noted that in such cases processing quantities can increase the complexity of the cognitive process, thus making it slower [ Pantsar, 2019b ; 2021a ]. Experiments show that even in cases where other cognitive processes would save time in making the right decision, the proto-arithmetical abilities are triggered. 39 This speaks for the general evolutionary advantage of possessing proto-arithmetical abilities. After all, given that applying the proto-arithmetical abilities makes decisions slower, there is likely to be some pay-off for the decrease in speed. Given the early evolutionary origins of the object-tracking system and the approximate-number system, it is tempting to explain this advantage by the proto-arithmetical abilities’ helping to detect the structure of the world in terms of macro-level objects. However, I recognize that it is at least a feasible possibility that such truth tracking fails. Ultimately, if all observations of our surroundings are filtered through cognitive core systems, we may not be able to determine the structure of the world entirely independently of those systems. Indeed, if my argument in this section is along the right lines, this extends from everyday experience of our local surroundings to modern scientific theories. By including mathematics in our scientific explanations, we are always working in a context influenced by the proto-mathematical abilities. In this context, it is to be expected that mathematics has scientific applications, and that mathematical knowledge appears to us as objective.

The purpose of this paper has been to explain from an epistemologically feasible basis why many mathematicians, philosophers, and laypeople believe in the objectivity of mathematical knowledge. However, one crucial question remains: is mathematical knowledge in fact objective? Conforming to Wright’s [ 1992 ] analysis of objectivity, I believe there are good reasons to consider at least basic arithmetical knowledge to be objective. The enculturated development of proto-arithmetical abilities into arithmetic makes it possible that there are unknown mathematical truths, thus fulfilling the criterion of epistemic constraint. This of course depends on the specific cultural context. The arithmetical truth |$2+3=5$| appears to be such an unknown truth for cultures like the Pirahã. 40 One could claim that since their language does not contain the necessary numerals to express such truths, their cultural context is not relevant here. But this is a problem only for the conventionalist position. If they did develop arithmetic based on their proto-arithmetical ability, they would end up holding |$2+3=5$| as an arithmetical truth. For our culture, unsolved problems like the Goldbach conjecture can be unknown truths. 41

Also the criterion of cognitive command seems to be fulfilled, since there are disagreements over arithmetical truths that are not blameless. If basic arithmetical truths are determined by proto-arithmetical abilities, Dostoevsky’s character believing in |$2+2=5$| would be mistaken and blameworthy: his belief would not follow the proto-arithmetical foundation of arithmetic, namely, his belief in |$2+2=5$| would conflict with his experiences in subitizing and/or estimating groups of objects. Finally, the wider cosmological role is fulfilled since arithmetic clearly has applications in science and everyday life. Whether these applications are ultimately indispensable is not crucial, since their fruitfulness in explanations is not tied to indispensability.

However, even if basic arithmetic can be considered to be objective, this is not to say that all mathematical knowledge is objective in the same sense. Members of a certain culture might not end up believing that, say, |$(-4)*(-4)=16$|⁠ , which seems to be only partly determined by proto-arithmetical abilities. And when we extend the account beyond arithmetic, the part played by conventions can become increasingly prominent. To the extent that mathematics is based on proto-mathematical cognition (and in addition to proto-arithmetic, this can include feasibly at least proto-geometry, proto-set-theory, and proto-logic), there would always seem to be a partly objective foundation for it. But as the role of conventions becomes more important, can we still call such knowledge objective in the same sense as we would call arithmetical knowledge objective? Such an analysis is beyond the scope of this paper, but I do not see any fundamental difficulties in parts of mathematical knowledge being considered more objective than others.

Finally, if it is accepted that some part of mathematical knowledge is objective, we should consider the ontological status of the mathematical objects postulated in it. As I see it, the account proposed in this paper is consistent with different forms of platonism, without requiring any of them. I have argued that arithmetical truths are at least partly determined by our proto-arithmetical abilities, but of course this does not rule out the possibility that numbers or structures as arithmetical objects could exist independently of the thoughts, languages, and practices of human subjects. What I have argued is that no such assumption needs to be made to provide a feasible epistemology of arithmetic.

How about the ontologically lighter versions of platonism, such as the accounts of Rayo and Linnebo? I contend that my account is consistent also with mathematical objects existing in this ‘thin’ sense, because the existence of abstract objects is not ruled out. My account does not require postulating mathematical objects even in the thin sense, but it can explain why the discourse involving abstract mathematical objects makes sense. In particular, the present account of mathematics as the product of the enculturated development based on proto-mathematical abilities can feasibly complement the accounts of both Rayo and Linnebo, since it can provide an explanation for why we end up accepting some mathematical truths and adopting some abstraction principles. Indeed, this seems to give a promising account of what the ‘thin’ existence of objects could mean in a non-conventionalist framework.

† This research was made possible by grants from the Alfred Kordelin Foundation and the Finnish Cultural Foundation. I would like to thank Regina E. Fabry for providing many helpful comments on an earlier version of the manuscript. I also want to thank the two anonymous reviewers for their comments. An early version of this work was presented at the workshop ‘Ontology in arithmetic and logic’ at l’Université du Québec à Montréal; I am grateful to the organizer Jean-Charles Pelland and all the participants at the workshop. Special thanks are in place to Bahram Assadian, Stefan Buijsman, Øystein Linnebo, Christopher Peacocke, Dirk Schlimm, and Andrea Sereni for helpful discussions.

1 Following a common custom in the literature ( e.g. , [ Dummett, 2006 ]), I will use the term ‘mind-independent’ to refer to something that is not dependent on human conventions, practices, languages, and thoughts.

2 Here I proceed with the custom that Platonism with capital ‘P’ refers specifically to Plato’s philosophy whereas platonism with a lower case ‘p’ refers to a more general realist metaphysical position on mathematics. Tait [2001] has suggested that instead of platonism, it would be clearer to talk about ‘realism’ than platonism. For the sake of terminological congruity with the relevant literature, however, I will follow the more common custom.

3 I call this view both ‘nativism’ and ‘cognitive nativism’ in this paper.

4 I assume here that it is accepted that true arithmetical beliefs constitute knowledge. Of course not all beliefs based on evolutionarily developed capacities are knowledge.

5 This move from the existence of mathematical objects to the objectivity of mathematical discourse is often referred to as ‘Kreisel’s Dictum’ in the literature. This is due to Dummett, who alludes to Kreisel’s review of Wittgenstein’s Remarks on the Foundations of Mathematics in which he supposedly points out that ‘the problem is not the existence of mathematical objects but the objectivity of mathematical statements’ [ Dummett, 1978 , p. xxxvii]. However, in that review Kreisel does not express this view explicitly and it is unclear where, and indeed if, he ever did that.

6 Although both of those questions will be treated in the final section.

7 Like Tait [2001] , in this paper I treat objectivity of mathematics and objectivity of mathematical discourse in an interchangeable manner. Furthermore, I assume that successful mathematical discourse can achieve knowledge.

8 [ Shapiro, 2007 ] also includes the criteria of response dependency and judgment dependency in his analysis of Wright’s criteria for mathematical discourse. Here I do not include them as I do not believe they add anything substantial to the analysis of the criteria of cognitive command in the present context.

9 For the present purposes this exposition is sufficient, but it should be noted that the matter is complicated. It does not follow that any particular mathematical truth would be unknowable, since the unprovable sentences depend on the particular axiomatizations and encodings. Nevertheless, Gödel’s [ 1931 ] first incompleteness theorem implies that no single formal axiomatic system proves all mathematical truths (see [ Pantsar, 2009 ]).

10 One potential exception is a questionnaire that revealed 82.4 |$\%$| of ‘professional mathematicians’ believed in the objectivity of mathematical knowledge [ Müller-Hill, 2009 ]. But this figure was based on an open Internet questionnaire and we cannot know for sure that the participants were in fact mathematicians. Moreover, other data gathered from the same questionnaire suggest that the same mathematicians were in fact inconsistent in their knowledge ascriptions. For a critical review of the study and its interpretation, see [ Pantsar, 2015b ].

11 For example, it could be that the appearance of objectivity comes from educational practices.

12 From here on, when I write about conventionalism, I am always referring to its strict version.

13 An interesting question is how intuitionist philosophy of mathematics should be understood in this regard. According to Shapiro [2007] , the original intuitionists like Heyting [1931] and Brouwer [1948] did not believe in the objectivity of mathematical knowledge, whereas at least some modern intuitionists, like Tennant [1997] , do.

14 This is not to say that in post-modernist philosophy such points of view are not endorsed, but I see no reason to engage with views such as those of Feyerabend [1975] here.

15 This point about multiplying two negative integers is made by various mathematicians, e.g. , [ Stewart, 2006 ].

16 This is a highly contested claim indeed. Field’s [ 1980 ] argument is that Newtonian mechanics can be reconstructed without appeal to mathematical notions. The book is called Science without Numbers , but Shapiro [2000] and others have claimed that what Field actually does in his nominalization project is remove the mathematical structure of numbers and replace it with another mathematical structure of Newtonian space and time. For more details, see [ Pantsar, 2009 ; Shapiro, 2000 ].

17 See [ Lange, 2013 ; 2017 ] for a defence of this view and [ Saatsi, 2011 ; 2016 ] for a contrary position. For a commentary on the debate, see [ Pantsar, 2018b ].

18 As shown in the end of this section, the matter is not straightforward for all accounts of platonism. However, I will also show that for all platonist accounts, the criterion of wider cosmological role poses more problems.

19 This is called Hume’s principle in the literature, following Boolos [ 1998 , p. 181].

20 For present purposes, it is not necessary to go into the differences of the accounts of Linnebo and the neo-Fregeans, but it should be noted that the two accounts are not equivalent. One of the fundamental differences Linnebo sees is that his account does not require the ‘syntactic priority thesis’ stating a type of priority of syntactic categories over ontological ones [ Linnebo, 2018a , p. xii].

21 The expression |$\exists!_{n}x(Fx)$| means that there exist exactly n values of x for which it holds that Fx .

22 Another possibility is that numbers exist in the possible world independently of cognitive agents, but assuming a platonist ontology of mind-independent objects would appear to go against the spirit of the subtle version of platonism and trivial existence of numbers that Rayo argues for.

23 To be precise, as mentioned earlier, this is the case if mathematics is indispensable for the scientific explanation in question, i.e. , the application of mathematics makes it possible to explain non-mathematical scientific facts that cannot be explained without mathematics.

24 For overviews of the development in recent years, both empirical and philosophical, see e.g. [ Cohen Kadosh and Dowker, 2015 ; Bangu, 2018 ; Pantsar and Dutilh Novaes, 2020 ].

25 Of course the possibility of mind-independent mathematical objects is not denied in evolutionary nativism. Platonism and nativism are not necessarily metaphysically contradictory positions, even though they seem to clash in terms of epistemology.

26 I have also proposed [ 2018a ] that the word ‘number’ should be reserved for arithmetic, while it would be clearer to speak of ‘numerosities’ for the proto-arithmetical abilities. A similar distinction is suggested by De Cruz et al. [2010] , as well as Núñez [2017] who proposes the term ‘quantical’ ability for what I call proto-arithmetical.

27 Carey [2009] calls the two systems core cognitive to emphasise their independence from other cognitive systems.

28 D’Errico et al. [ 2018 ] argue that this development can in fact be tracked back at least to roughly 70,000–62,000 BC, to artifacts such as a notched hyena femur bone found at the Les Pradelles Mousterian site in France.

29 Unfortunately, very little has remained to tell us how this process has taken place. From ancient Greece, higher-level mathematical works by the likes of Archimedes and Euclid have survived but although they were used for educational purposes, not much is known about early mathematical education and what role it played [ Morgan, 1999 ]. Mueller [1991] notes that arithmetic was apparently widely known in fifth century (BCE) Athens but it is not clear that this knowledge was acquired in schools. See [ Fried, 2012 ] for more.

30 While the arithmetical content is largely equivalent cross-culturally, there are many differences in educational practices, including the kind of tools that are used (pen and paper, abacus, calculators, etc .). See [ Fabry and Pantsar, 2019 ] for more on the impact of cognitive tools on mathematical problem-solving processes.

31 This dichotomy can still be fruitful for explanatory purposes, however, which is why I refer to it at times in the rest of the paper.

32 This principle is called neuronal recycling . Anderson [2015] has proposed the more general principle of neural reuse instead, which has been argued by Jones [2020] and Fabry [2020] to be a better fit for understanding the development of arithmetical cognition.

33 This should not be confused with the claim that cultural evolution is not fundamentally a biological phenomenon. The two terms are used here as different categories of explanation without any metaphysical claims associated.

34 This idea of a feedback loop is a generalization of the feedback loop that according to Fabry [2018] connects enculturation and ‘epistemic engineering’ [ Sterelny, 2014 ; Menary, 2014 ; 2015 ], which she sees as one constitutive process of cumulative cultural evolution.

35 How individual contributions are introduced and accepted by mathematical communities, thus leading to mathematical innovation, is a highly interesting research question. See, e.g. , [ Wagner, 2017 ] for discussion on how mathematical practices are established.

36 I thank an anonymous reviewer for pointing this out.

37 Indeed, they are shared (at least to a large degree) with many non-human animals.

38 I add the scare-quotes to ‘designed’ in paraphrasing Maddy for a good reason: on the present account, there is no justification for claiming that proto-mathematical abilities are designed in any way. Indeed, I see the kind of teleological explanation that Maddy proposes as quite problematic.

39 This has been confirmed in adult humans by tests in which the subjects where asked whether two number symbols are the same. This requires no ability with quantities (it is enough to recognize whether the shapes of the symbols are the same), but the data show a clear ‘distance effect’ in the reaction times: for example, the pair 71 65 takes more time than the pair 79 65 [ Hinrichs et al. , 1981 ; Pinel et al. , 2001 ]. The best explanation for this is that even though we know the task, we cannot help processing the number symbols as quantities, which triggers the approximate-number system. Since there’s more distance between 79 and 65 than 71 and 65, the characteristics of the approximate-number system predict that the former case is processed faster. See [ Pantsar, 2019b ] for more.

40 This is still debated. Overmann and Coolidge [2013] , for example, have argued for the possibility that number concepts could be independent of language, which would imply that the Pirahã could possess number concepts even though their language does not contain corresponding numerals. If that is indeed the case and the truth of |$2+3=5$| is thought to be within the grasp of monolingual Pirahã, the sum in this example can be replaced by one involving larger numbers. Overmann and Coolidge ( ibid .) accept that learning exact large numbers demands language.

41 The Goldbach conjecture states that every even integer greater than two can be expressed as the sum of two prime numbers.

Agrillo, C [ 2015 ]: ‘ Numerical and arithmetic abilities in non-primate species ’, in [ Cohen Kadosh and Dowker, 2015 ] , pp. 214 – 236 .

Anderson, M [ 2015 ]: After Phrenology: Neural Reuse and the Interactive Brain. Cambridge, Mass .: MIT Press .

Google Scholar

Google Preview

Ansari, D [ 2008 ]: ‘ Effects of development and enculturation on number representation in the brain ’, Nature Reviews Neuroscience 9 , 278 – 291 .

Arora, S , and Barak B [ 2007 ]: Computational Complexity: A Modern Approach. Cambridge University Press .

Baker, A [ 2005 ]: ‘ Are there genuine mathematical explanations of physical phenomena? ’, Mind 114 , 223 – 238 .

Baker, A [ 2009 ]: ‘ Mathematical explanation in science . British Journal of Philosophy of Science 60 , 611 – 633 .

Balaguer, M [ 2009 ]: ‘ Realism and anti-realism in mathematics ’, in Irvine, A. ed., Philosophy of Mathematics , pp. 35 – 101 . Handbook of the Philosophy of Science. North Holland .

Bangu, S , ed. [ 2018 ]: Naturalizing Logico-Mathematical Knowledge . New York : Routledge .

Beck, J [ 2017 ]: ‘ Can bootstrapping explain concept learning? ’, Cognition 158 , 110 – 121 .

Benacerraf, P [ 1973 ]: ‘ Mathematical truth ’, The Journal of Philosophy 70 , 661 – 679 .

Benacerraf, P , and Putnam H , eds [ 1983 ]: Philosophy of Mathematics: Selected Readings, 2nd ed. Cambridge University Press .

Bloom, P [ 2000 ]: How Children Learn the Meanings of Words. Cambridge, Mass .: MIT Press .

Bloor, D [ 1976 ]: Knowledge and Social Imagery, London : Routledge and Kegan Paul .

Boolos, G [ 1998 ]: Logic, Logic and Logic . Jeffrey R. and Burgess, J.P. eds. Cambridge, Mass. : Harvard University Press .

Boyd, R , and Richerson P.J [ 1985 ]: Culture and the Evolutionary Process. University of Chicago Press .

Boyd, R , and Richerson P.J [ 2005 ]: Not by Genes Alone. University of Chicago Press .

Boyer, C [ 1991 ]: A History of Mathematics . 2nd ed. Hoboken, N.J. : Wiley .

Brouwer, L.E.J [ 1948 ]: ‘ Consciousness, philosophy and mathematics ’, in [ Benacerraf and Putnam, 1983 ] , pp. 90 – 96 .

Brown, J.R [ 2008 ]: Philosophy of Mathematics: A Contemporary Introduction to the World of Proofs and Pictures . 2nd ed. New York : Routledge .

Butterworth, B [ 1999 ]: What Counts: How Every Brain is Hardwired for Math . New York : The Free Press .

Cantlon, J.F , and Brannon E.M [ 2006 ]: ‘ Shared system for ordering small and large numbers in monkeys and humans ’, Psychological Science 17 , 402 – 407 .

Cantor, G [ 1883 ]: ‘ Über unendliche, lineare Punktmannigfaltigkeiten, 5 ’, Mathematische Annalen 21 , 545 – 586 .

Carey, S [ 2009 ]: The Origin of Concepts. Oxford University Press .

Carey, S , Shusterman A , Haward P , and Distefano R [ 2017 ]: ‘ Do analog number representations underlie the meanings of young children’s verbal numerals? ’, Cognition 168 , 243 – 255 .

Cheung, P , and Le Corre M [ 2018 ]: ‘ Parallel individuation supports numerical comparisons in preschoolers ’, Journal of Numerical Cognition 4 , 380 – 409 .

Chihara, C [ 1973 ]: Ontology and the Vicious Circle Principle . Ithaca, N.Y. : Cornell University Press .

Chihara, C [ 1990 ]: Constructibility and Mathematical Existence . Oxford University Press .

Chihara, C [ 2005 ]: ‘ Nominalism ’, in Shapiro, S. ed., The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Mathematics and Logic , pp. 483 – 514 . Oxford University Press .

Cohen Kadosh, R.C , and Dowker A [ 2015 ]: The Oxford Handbook of Numerical Cognition . Oxford University Press .

Colyvan, M [ 2001 ]: The Indispensability of Mathematics. Oxford University Press .

De Cruz, H [ 2016 ]: ‘ Numerical cognition and mathematical realism ’, Philosopher’s Imprint 16 , 1 – 13 .

De Cruz, H , Neth H , and Schlimm D [ 2010 ]: ‘ The cognitive basis of arithmetic ’, in Löwe B. and Müller, T. eds, PhiMSAMP. Philosophy of Mathematics: Sociological Aspects and Mathematical Practice , pp. 59 – 106 . London : College Publications .

d’Errico, F , Doyon L , Colagé I , Queffelec A , Le Vraux E , Giacobini G , Vandermeersch B , and Maureille B [ 2018 ]: ‘ From number sense to number symbols: An archaeological perspective ’, Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences 373 , Article 20160518 . doi.org/10.1098/rstb.2016.0518 .

Dehaene, S [ 1997/2011 ]: The Number Sense: How the Mind Creates Mathematics . 2nd ed. Oxford University Press .

Dehaene, S [ 2001 ]: ‘ Précis of the number sense ’, Mind and Language 16 , 16 – 36 .

Dehaene, S [ 2009 ]: Reading in the Brain: The New Science of How We Read . London : Penguin .

Dehaene, S , and Cohen L [ 2007 ]: ‘ Cultural recycling of cortical maps ’, Neuron 56 , 384 – 398 .

Dehaene, S , Izard V , Spelke E , and Pica P [ 2008 ]: ‘ Log or linear? Distinct intuitions of the number scale in Western and Amazonian indigene cultures ’, Science 320 , 1217 – 1220 .

Dostoevsky, F [ 1864 ]: Notes from Underground . Pevear R. and Volokhonsky, L. trans. London : Vintage Classics , 1994 .

Dummett, M [ 1978 ]: Truth and Other Enigmas , Cambridge, Mass. : Harvard University Press .

Dummett, M [ 2006 ]: Thought and Reality. Oxford University Press .

Fabry, R.E [ 2017 ]: ‘ Cognitive innovation, cumulative cultural evolution, and enculturation ’, Journal of Cognition and Culture 17 , 375 – 395 .

Fabry, R.E [ 2018 ]: ‘ Betwixt and between: The enculturated predictive processing approach to cognition ’, Synthese 195 , 2483 – 2518 .

Fabry, R.E [ 2020 ]: ‘ The cerebral, extra-cerebral bodily, and socio-cultural dimensions of enculturated arithmetical cognition ’, Synthese 197 , 3685 – 3720 .

Fabry, R , and Pantsar M [ 2019 ]: ‘ A fresh look at research strategies in cognitive science: The case of enculturated mathematical problem solving ’, Synthese . doi.org/10.1007/s11229-019-02276-9 .

Feyerabend, P [ 1975 ]: Against Method . London : Verso .

Field, H [ 1980 ]: Science Without Numbers . Princeton University Press .

Frege, G [ 1884 ]: Foundations of Arithmetic . Austin, J.L. trans., 1953 . Oxford : Blackwell .

Frege, G 1893/1903]: Grundgesetze der Arithmetik. Jena: Pohle. Published in English as Basic Laws of Arithmetic , Ebert Philip A. and Rossberg, Marcus trans. Oxford University Press , 2013 .

Fried, M.N [ 2012 ]: ‘ Euclid’s book on the regular solids: Its place in the Elements and its educational value ’, in Sriraman, B. ed., Crossroads in the History of Mathematics and Mathematics Education , pp. 173 – 196 . Charlotte, N.C. : Information Age Publishing .

Gödel, K [ 1931 ]: ‘ On formally undecidable propositions ’, in Collected Works, Volume I , pp. 145 – 195 . Oxford University Press , 1986.

Gödel, K [ 1983 ]: ‘ What is Cantor’s continuum problem ’, in [ Benacerraf and Putnam, 1983 ] , pp. 470 – 485 .

Gordon, P [ 2004 ]: ‘ Numerical cognition without words: Evidence from Amazonia ’, Science 306 , 496 – 499 .

Halberda, J , and Feigenson L [ 2008 ]: ‘ Set representations required for acquisition of the natural number concept ’, Behavioral and Brain Sciences 31 , 655 – 656 .

Hale, B , and Wright C [ 2001 ]: The Reason’s Proper Study . Oxford : Clarendon Press .

Hale, B , and Wright C [ 2009 ]: ‘ The metaontology of abstraction ’, in D. Chalmers, Manley O , and Wasserman R , eds, Metametaphysics: New Essays on the Foundations of Ontology , pp. 178 – 212 .. Oxford University Press .

Hauser, M. D , Carey S , and Hauser L.B [ 2000 ]: ‘ Spontaneous number representation in semi-free-ranging rhesus monkeys ’, Proceedings of the Royal Society of London B: Biological Sciences 267 , 829 – 833 . doi.org/10.1098/rspb.2000.1078

Hellman, G [ 1989 ]: Mathematics Without Numbers . Oxford University Press .

Hellman, G [ 2005 ]: ‘ Structuralism ’, in [ Shapiro, 2005 ] , pp. 536 – 562 .

Henrich, J [ 2015 ]: The Secret of Our Success: How Culture Is Driving Human Evolution, Domesticating Our Species, and Making Us Smarter. Princeton University Press .

Heyes, C [ 2018 ]: Cognitive Gadgets: The Cultural Evolution of Thinking . Cambridge, Mass. : Harvard University Press .

Heyting, A [ 1931 ]: ‘ The intuitionistic foundations of mathematics ’, in [ Benacerraf and Putnam, 1983 ] , pp. 52 – 61 .

Hinrichs, J.V , Yurko D.S , and Hu J.M [ 1981 ]: ‘ Two-digit number comparison: Use of place information ’, Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Perception and Performance 7 , 890 – 901 .

Hunt, S , Low J , and Burns K.C [ 2008 ]: ‘ Adaptive numerical competency in a food-hoarding songbird ’, Proceedings of the Royal Society of London B: Biological Sciences 275 , 2373 – 2379 . doi.org/10.1098/rspb.2008.0702

Ifrah, G [ 1998 ]: The Universal History of Numbers: From Prehistory to their Invention of the Computer. London : Harville Press .

Izard, V , Pica P , Spelke E.S , and Dehaene S [ 2008 ]: ‘ Exact equality and successor function: Two key concepts on the path towards understanding exact numbers ’, Philosophical Psychology 21 , 491 – 505 .

Jones, M [ 2020 ]: ‘ Numerals and neural reuse ’, Synthese 197 , 3657 – 3681 .

Kitcher, P [ 1983 ]: The Nature of Mathematical Knowledge . New York : Oxford University Press .

Lakoff, G , and Núñez R [ 2000 ]: Where Mathematics Comes From. New York : Basic Books .

Laland, K.N [ 2017 ]: Darwin’s Unfinished Symphony: How Culture Made the Human Mind. Princeton University Press .

Lange, M [ 2013 ]: ‘ What makes a scientific explanation distinctively mathematical? ’, British Journal of Philosophy of Science 64 , 485 – 511 .

Lange, M [ 2017 ]: Because Without Cause: Non-causal Explanations in Science and Mathematics. Oxford University Press .

Linnebo, Ø. [ 2017 ]: Philosophy of Mathematics. Princeton University Press .

Linnebo, Ø. [ 2018a ]: Thin Objects. Oxford University Press .

Linnebo, Ø. [ 2018b ]: ‘ Platonism in the philosophy of mathematics ’, Zalta E.N , ed., The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy ( Spring , 2020 ). https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2018/entries/platonism-mathematics . Accessed March 2021.

Maddy, P [ 2014 ]: ‘ A second philosophy of arithmetic ’, The Review of Symbolic Logic 7 , 222 – 249 .

Menary, R [ 2014 ]: ‘ Neuronal recycling, neural plasticity and niche construction ’, Mind and Language 29 , 286 – 303 .

Menary, R [ 2015 ]: Mathematical Cognition: A Case of Enculturation. Frankfurt am Main : Open MIND, MIND Group .

Mill, J.S [ 1843 ]: ‘ A system of logic ’, in Robson, J.M. ed., Collected Works of John Stuart Mill , Vols 7 and 8 . University of Toronto Press .

Morgan, T.J [ 1999 ]: ‘ Literate education in classical Athens ’, The Classical Quarterly 49 , 46 – 61 .

Mueller, I [ 1991 ]: ‘ Mathematics and education: Some notes on the Platonic program ’, Apeiron 24 , 85 – 104 .

Müller-Hill, E [ 2009 ]: ‘ Formalizability and knowledge ascriptions in mathematical practice ’, Philosophia Scientiae 13 , 21 – 43 .

Nieder, A , and Dehaene S [ 2009 ]: ‘ Representation of number in the brain ’, Annual Review of Neuroscience 32 , 185 – 208 .

Núñez, R [ 2017 ]: ‘ Is there really an evolved capacity for number? ’, Trends in Cognitive Science 21 , 409 – 424 .

Overmann, K.A , and Coolidge F.L [ 2013 ]: ‘ On the nature of numerosity and the role of language in developing number concepts: A reply to Everett ’, Current Anthropology 54 , 83 – 84 .

Pantsar, M [ 2009 ]: Truth, Proof and Gödelian Arguments: A Defence of Tarskian Truth in Mathematics . Philosophical Studies from the University of Helsinki , Vol. 23 .

Pantsar, M [ 2014 ]: ‘ An empirically feasible approach to the epistemology of arithmetic ’, Synthese 191 , 4201 – 4229 .

Pantsar, M [ 2015a ]: ‘ In search of aleph-null: How infinity can be created ’, Synthese 192 , 2489 – 2511 .

Pantsar, M [ 2015b ]: ‘ Assessing the empirical philosophy of mathematics ’, Discipline filosofiche 25 , 111 – 130 . doi.org/10.1400/236780 .

Pantsar, M [ 2016 ]: ‘ The modal status of contextually a priori arithmetical truths ’, in Boccuni F. and Sereni, A. eds., Philosophy of Mathematics: Objectivity, Cognition, and Proof , 67 – 81 . Springer . doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-31644-4_5 .

Pantsar, M [ 2018a ]: ‘ Early numerical cognition and mathematical processes ’, Theoria 33 , 285 – 304 .

Pantsar, M [ 2018b ]: ‘ Mathematical explanations and mathematical applications ’, in Sriraman, B. ed., Handbook of Mathematics of the Arts and Sciences . Springer . doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-70658-0_30-1

Pantsar, M [ 2019a ]: ‘ The enculturated move from proto-arithmetic to arithmetic ’, Frontiers in Psychology 10 , 1454.

Pantsar, M [ 2019b ]: ‘ Cognitive and computational complexity: Considerations from mathematical problem solving ’, Erkenntnis . doi.org/10.1007/s10670-019-00140-3 .

Pantsar, M [ 2020 ]: ‘ Mathematical cognition and enculturation: Introduction to the Synthese special issue ’, Synthese 197 , 3647 – 3655 . doi.org/10.1007/s11229-019-02478-1 .

Pantsar, M [ 2021a ]: ‘ Descriptive complexity, computational tractability, and the logical and cognitive foundations of mathematics ’, Minds and Machines 31 , 75 – 98 . doi.org/10.1007/s11023-020-09545-4 .

Pantsar, M [ 2021b ]: ‘ Bootstrapping of integer concepts: The stronger deviant-interpreation challenge (and how to solve it) ’, Synthese doi.org/10.1007/s11229-021-03046-2 .

Pantsar, M , and Dutilh Novaes C , eds [ 2020 ]: ‘ Mathematical cognition and enculturation ’. Synthese Special Issue. Synthese 197 . doi.org/10.1007/s11229-019-02478-1 .

Panza, M , and Sereni A [ 2013 ]: Plato’s Problem: An Introduction to Mathematical Platonism. Springer .

Peacocke, C [ 1993 ]: ‘ How are a piori truths possible? ’, European Journal of Philosophy 1 , 175 – 199 .

Pepperberg, I.M [ 2012 ]: ‘ Further evidence for addition and numerical competence by a grey parrot (Psittacus erithacus) ’, Animal Cognition 15 , 711 – 717 .

Pica, P , Lemer C , Izard V , and Dehaene S [ 2004 ]: ‘ Exact and approximate arithmetic in an Amazonian indigene group ’, Science 306 , 499 – 503 .

Pincock, C [ 2012 ]: Mathematics and Scientific Representation . Oxford University Press .

Pinel, P , Dehaene S , Riviere D , and LeBihan D [ 2001 ]: ‘ Modulation of parietal activation by semantic distance in a number comparison task ’, Neuroimage 14 , 1013 – 1026 .

Plato [ 1992 ]: The Republic . 2nd ed. Grube, G.M.A. trans. Indianapolis : Hackett Publishing Company .

Putnam, H [ 1967 ]: ‘ Mathematics without foundations ’, Journal of Philosophy 64 , 5 – 22 .

Quine, W.V [ 1966 ]: ‘ The scope of language of science ’, in Quine, W.V. The Ways of Paradox and Other Essays , pp. 215 – 232 . New York : Random House .

Quine, W.V [ 1969 ]: ‘ Existence and quantification ’, in Quine, W.V. Ontological Relativity and Other Essays , pp. 91 – 113 . New York : Columbia University .

Rayo, A [ 2013 ]: The Construction of Logical Space. Oxford University Press .

Rayo, A [ 2015 ]: ‘ Nominalism, trivialism, logicism ’, Philosophia Mathematica (3) 23 , 65 – 86 .

Reutlinger, A , and Saatsi J , eds [ 2018 ]: Explanation Beyond Causation . Oxford University Press .

Rugani, R , Fontanari L , Simoni E , Regolin L , and Vallortigara G [ 2009 ]: ‘ Arithmetic in newborn chicks ’, Proceedings of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences 276 , 2451 – 2460 . doi.org/10.1098/rspb.2009.0044

Saatsi, J [ 2011 ]: ‘ The enhanced indispensability argument: Representational versus explanatory role of mathematics in science ’, British Journal of Philosophy of Science 62 , 143 – 154 .

Saatsi, J [ 2016 ]: ‘ On the “indispensable explanatory role of mathematics” ’ Mind 125 , 1045 – 1070 .

Sampson, G [ 1985 ]: Writing Systems: A Linguistic Introduction. Stanford, Calif .: Stanford University Press .

Sarnecka, B.W , and Carey S [ 2008 ]: ‘ How counting represents number: What children must learn and when they learn it ’, Cognition 108 , 662 – 674 .

Shapiro, S [ 1997 ]: Philosophy of Mathematics: Structure and Ontology. Oxford University Press .

Shapiro, S [ 2000 ]: Thinking About Mathematics . Oxford University Press .

Shapiro, S , ed. [2005]: The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Mathematics and Logic . Oxford University Press .

Shapiro, S [ 2007 ]: ‘ The objectivity of mathematics ’, Synthese 156 , 337 – 381 .

Spelke, E.S [ 2000 ]: ‘ Core knowledge ’, American Psychologist 55 , 1233.

Spelke, E.S [ 2011 ]: ‘ Quinean bootstrapping or Fodorian combination? Core and constructed knowledge of number ’, Behavioral and Brain Sciences 34 , 149 – 150 .

Starkey, P , and Cooper R.G [ 1980 ]: ‘ Perception of numbers by human infants ’, Science 210 , 1033 – 1035 .

Sterelny, K [ 2014 ]: The Evolved Apprentice: How Evolution Made Humans Unique. Jean Nicod Lectures; 4 . Cambridge, Mass. : MIT Press .

Stewart, I [ 2006 ]: Letters to a Young Mathematician , New York : Basic Books .

Tait, W.W [ 2001 ]: ‘ Beyond the axioms: The question of objectivity in mathematics ’, Philosophia Mathematica ( 3 ) 9 , 21 – 36 .

Tennant, N [ 1997 ]: The Taming of the True . Oxford University Press .

Tomasello, M [ 1999 ]: The Cultural Origins of Human Cognition . Cambridge, Mass. : Harvard University Press .

vanMarle, K , Chu F.W , Mou Y , Seok J.H , Rouder J. and Geary D.C. [ 2018 ]: ‘ Attaching meaning to the number words: Contributions of the object tracking and approximate number systems ’, Developmental Science 21 , e12495 .

Wagner, R [ 2017 ]: Making and Breaking Mathematical Sense: Histories and Philosophies of Mathematical Practice. Princeton University Press .

Wittgenstein, L [ 1976 ]: Lectures on the Foundations of Mathematics, Cambridge 1939 , Diamond C , ed. University of Chicago Press .

Wright, C [ 1992 ]: Truth and Objectivity . Cambridge, Mass. : Harvard University Press .

Wynn, K [ 1992 ]: ‘ Addition and subtraction by human infants ’, Nature 358 , 749 – 751 .

Yoshimura, J [ 1997 ]: ‘ The evolutionary origins of periodical cicadas during Ice Ages ’, The American Naturalist 49 , 112 – 124 .

Zach, R [ 2019 ]: ‘ Hilbert’s program ’, in Zalta, E.N. ed., The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy ( Spring , 2019 ). https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/hilbert-program . Accessed March 2021.

Email alerts

Citing articles via.

  • Recommend to your Library

Affiliations

  • Online ISSN 1744-6406
  • Copyright © 2024 Oxford University Press
  • About Oxford Academic
  • Publish journals with us
  • University press partners
  • What we publish
  • New features  
  • Open access
  • Institutional account management
  • Rights and permissions
  • Get help with access
  • Accessibility
  • Advertising
  • Media enquiries
  • Oxford University Press
  • Oxford Languages
  • University of Oxford

Oxford University Press is a department of the University of Oxford. It furthers the University's objective of excellence in research, scholarship, and education by publishing worldwide

  • Copyright © 2024 Oxford University Press
  • Cookie settings
  • Cookie policy
  • Privacy policy
  • Legal notice

This Feature Is Available To Subscribers Only

Sign In or Create an Account

This PDF is available to Subscribers Only

For full access to this pdf, sign in to an existing account, or purchase an annual subscription.

UNN INFO

Home » WAEC Mathematics Answers 2024 [Essay/OBJ] Questions is Out

2024 WAEC Mathematics Answers Released – See Waec Maths Questions for Objectives & Essay Here.

The Waec Mathematics Answers 2024 questions are now available. The West African Examination Council (WAEC) General Mathematics essay and objective paper will now be written on Thursday, 30th May 2024.

The WAEC Mathematics 2 (Essay) paper will start at 9:30 am and will last for 2hrs 30mins while the Waec Mathematics 1 (Objective) exam will commence at 3:00 pm and will last for 1hr 30mins. In this post, you will be seeing the WAEC Maths questions and answers 2024 for candidates who will participate in the examination from past questions.

The questions and answers below on WAEC Mathematics have been provided to assist candidates in understanding the required standards expected in the WAEC Mathematics Examination. There is nothing Waec Mathematics Expo 2024 online.

waec mathematics answers

2024 WAEC Mathematics Question and Answer.

PAPER 2 [Essay] Answer any … questions. Write your answers in the answer booklet provided.

1. (a) Solve: 7x + 4  < (4x + 3). (b) Salem, Sunday and Shaka shared a sum of N 1,100.00. For every N2.00 that Salem gets, Sunday gets fifty kobo and for every N 4.00 Sunday gets, Shaka gets N 2.00. Find Shaka’s share.

2. ( a) The angle of depression of a boat from the mid-point of a vertical cliff is 35°. If the boat is 120 m from the foot of the cliff, calculate the height of the cliff.

(b) Towns P and Q are x km apart. Two motorists set out at the same time from P to Q at steady speeds of 60 km/h and 80 km/h. The faster motorist got to Q 30 minutes earlier than the other. Find the value of x.

3. (a) A boy 1.2 m tall, stands 6 m away from the foot of a vertical lamp pole 4.2 m long. If the lamp is at the tip of the pole, r epresent this information in a diagram.

(b) Calculate the:

(i) length of the shadow of the boy cast by the lamp.

4. (a) The present ages of a father and his son are in the ratio 10 : 3. If the son is 15 years old now, in how many years will the ratio of their ages be 2 : 1?

(b) The arithmetic mean of x, y and z is 6 while that of x, y, z, t, u, v and w is 9. Calculate the arithmetic mean of t, u, v and w.

Mathematics waec

6. A point H is 20m away from the foot of a tower on the same horizontal ground. From point H, the angle of elevation of point (P) on the tower and the top (T) of the tower are 30o and 50o respectively.  Calculate, and correct 3 significant figures:

(a) /PT/; (b) The distance between H and the top of the tower; (c) The position of H if the angle of depression of H from the top of the tower is to be 40°.

Neco maths 2022

9. In the diagram, /AB/ = 8 km, /BC/ = 13 km, the bearing of A from B is 310° and the bearing of B from C is 230°. Calculate, correct to 3 significant figures,

(a) the distance AC;

(b) the bearing of C from A;

(c) how far east of B, C is

mathematics objective and essay

11. (a) In a class of 40 students, 18 passed Mathematics, 19 passed Accounts, 16 passed Economics, 5 Mathematics and Accounts only, 6 Mathematics only, 9 Accounts only, 2 Accounts and Economics only. If each student offered at least one of the subjects.

i. How many students failed in all the subjects?

ii. Find the percentage number who failed in at least one of Economics and Mathematics;

(b) Calculate the probability that a student selected at random failed in Accounts.

mathematics objective and essay

WAEC Mathematics Objective Questions 2024.

PAPER 1 (Objective) Answer ALL questions in this section. Shade your answer in the answer booklet provided.

1. In a school, 180 students offer mathematics or physics, or both. If 125  offer mathematics and 105 offer physics. How many students offer mathematics only? A.75       B. 80       C. 55       D. 125.

2. Find the value of x for which 3(2 4x + 3 ) = 96 A. 2       B. -2       C. ½       D. -1/2

3. The cost of renovating a 5m square room is N500. What is the cost of renovating a 10m square room? A. N1,000       B. N2,500       C. 2,000       D. N10,000

4. Find the rate of change of the total surface area S of a sphere with respect to its radius r when r = 2 A. 8       B. 16       C. 10       D. 14

5. Differentiate (cosӨ + sinӨ) 2 with respect to Ө. A. 2cos2Ө       B. 2sin2Ө       C. -2cos2Ө       D. -2sin2Ө

6. A binary operation * on the set of rational numbers is defined as x * y = 2x + [x 3 – y 3 /x + y]. find -1*2 A. 11       B. -11       C. 8       D. -8

7. A polynomial in x whose zeroes are 2, 1 and -3 is ______ A. x 3 – 7x + 6 B. x 3 + 7x – 6 C. x 3 – 7x –  6 D. x 3 + 7x + 6

8. Find the range of values of x for which 7x –  3 > 3x + 4 A. x < 7/4 B. x > 7/4 C. 7x < 4 D. -4x < 7

9. Some red balls were put in a basket containing 12 white balls and 16 blue balls. If the probability of picking a red ball from the basket is 3/7, how many red balls were introduced? A. 13       B.20       C. 12       D. 21

10. Convert 1231 4 to a number in base 6. A. 105 6 B. 301 6 C. 103 6 D. 501 6

11. Find the slope of the curve y = 3x 3 + 5x 2 – 3 at (-1, 5). A. 1       B. -1       C. 19       D. -19

12. Find the area of the region bounded by y = x 2 + x – 2 and x-axis. A. 9/2         B. -39/6         C. 8/3          D. 16/3

13. The minimum value of y = x 2 – 4x – 5 is ______ A. 2          B. -2         C.13          D. -13

14. There are 8 boys and 4 girls in a lift. What is the probability that the first person who steps out of the lift will be a boy? A. 3/4       B. 1/3       C. 2/3       D. 1/4

15. H varies directly as p and inversely as the square of y. If H = 1, p = 8 and y = 2, find H in terms of p and y. A. H = p /4y^2       B. H = 2p / y^2       C. H = p / 2 y^2       D. H = p / y^2

16. Solve 4x^2 – 16x + 15 A. X = 1 (1/2) or X = -2 (1/2)       B. X = 1 (1/2) or X = 2 (1/2)       C. X = 1 (1/2) or X = -1 (1/2)       D. X = -1 (1/2) or X = -2 (1/2)

17. If (0.25)^y = 32, find the value of y. A. y = -5/2       B. y = -3/2       B. y = 3/2       D. y = 5/2.

18. Simplify: log 6 – 3log 3 + 2/3log 27. A. 3log 2       B. Log 2       C. Log 3       D. 2log 3

19. Bala sold an article for 6,900.00 nairas and made a profit of 15 percent. Calculate his percentage profit if he had sold for 6600.00. A. 5 percent       B. 10 percent       C. 12 percent       D. 13 percent

20. If 3P = 4Q and 9P = 8Q-12, find the value of PQ. A. 12       B. 7       C. -7       D. -12

21. Evaluate 0.42 divided by 2.5 /0.5 x 2.05, leaving the answer in standard form. A. 1.639 x 10^2       B. 1.639 x 10^1       C. 1.639 x 10^-1       D. 1.639 x 10^-2.

22. A husband contributes 7% of his income into a fund and his wife contributes 4% of her income. If the husband earns N5,500 per annum (p.a) and his wife earns N4,000 p.a, find the sum of their contribution to the fund. A. N1,045                B. N605         C. N545         D. N490.

23. If the children share N10.50K among themselves in the ratio 6:7:8, How much is the largest share? A. N3.00         B. N3.50         C. N4.00         D. N4.50.

24. A trader makes a loss of 15% when selling an article. Find the ratio, selling price: cost price. A. 3:20         B. 3:17         C. 17:20         D. 20:23.

25. The ages of three men are in the ratio 3:4:5. If the difference between the ages of the oldest and youngest is 18 years, find the sum of the ages of the three men. A. 45 years         B. 72 years         C. 108 years         D. 216 years.

26. A bicycle wheel of a radius of 42cm is rolled over a distance of 66m. How many revolutions does it make? [Take π=22/7] A. 2.5         B. 5         C. 25         D. 50.

27. If 2x : (x+1) =3:2, what is the value of x? A. ½         B. 1         C. 1½         D. 3.

28. What is the probability of having an odd number in a single toss of a fair die? A. 1/6         B. 1/3         C. ½         C. 2/3.

PS: Once again, there is nothing like the waec maths expo. Do not fall victim to scammers online trying to obtain money from you with fake promises of having access to a live question paper before the exam. What we have on this page are likely exam questions from waec maths past questions and answers to serve as a revision guide.

Keep following, more questions and answers will be added soon.

WELCOME TO EXAMAFRICA.COM THE HOME OF EXCELLENT EXAM RESULTS

Examafrica.com is the only verified and trusted exam expo website for 100% legit jamb | waec | neco | nabteb | gce | ijmb & jupeb runz, for easy & fast contact 08164133799 || 08164133799.

  • 2022 WAEC GCE Mathematics Questions and Answers

November 25, 2022 Tonykamsy WAEC GCE 0

ijmb waec and neco runz runs

ExamAfrica.Com: Drop First While Others Copy From Us, We Are 100% Reliable And We Never Disappoint Our Subscribers.

2022 WAEC GCE Second series GENERAL MATHEMATICS ESSAY/OBJECTIVES QUESTIONS AND ANSWERS EXPO/RUNZ NOW AVAILABLE @ WWW.EXAMAFRICA.COM

Whether Your Village people Likes or Not, With ExamAfrica.Com A1 Must Locate You. Thank your Stars for finding the Best and Accurate Expo site for your Waec Gce Second series Jan/feb Mathematics Essay And Objectives (obj) 2022 Questions and Answers

NOTE: If You Want us To Assist You In Supplying Night Questions and Answers For The 2022 Waec Gce Second series Mathematics Essay And Objectives (obj) Questions and Answers Runz/Expo/dubs/chokes

You will Need to Subscribe with Us.

We Have Two Ways of Sending questions and answers to Students,Teachers, Principals and School Owners

Only-Password & LINK –> #500 MTN CARD

Password And LINK: MEANS The Pin to access our answer page Link online via https://www.examafrica.com/answerpage.Immediately after we confirm your subscription.The Pin will be sent to you to access our answers. Answers are sent to our subscribers A Night before exam

WhatsApp Fast Delivery –> #800 MTN CARD

Whatsapp Fast Delivery: This is one of the Best and fastest Delivery, The Questions and answers will be sent to you direct on WhatsApp after we confirmed your subscription. We’ll send both questions and answers to only our Subscribers A Night before exam. Ensure you Save Our WhatsApp num; 08164133799

Suggested Posts;

  • 2022 WAEC GCE Hausa Expo / GCE Igbo Questions / Yoruba 2022 Answers
  • 2022 Neco Gce Biology essay Questions and Answers (Expo)
  • Nabteb Gce Mathematics Essay And Obj (Objectives) /2022

CLICK HERE TO VIEW OUR ANSWER PAGE WITH YOUR PIN

HOW TO MAKE THE PAYMENT

WE ACCEPT MTN CARD PAYMENT OR BANK TRANSFER

PAYMENT THROUGH MTN RECHARGE CARD:

SEND THE FOLLOWING MTN CARD + SUBJECT + PHONE NUMBER TO 08164133799 AS TEXT MESSAGE ONLY: 08164133799 Only

(i)MTN-CARD (ii)AMOUNT PAID (iii)EXAM NAME (iv)PHONE NUMBER (v)SUBJECTS

PAYMENT THROUGH BANK:

Chat Us On WhatsApp for our Account Num: 08164133799

Text “I need Bank details”

PAYMENT FOR ALL SUBJECTS, GROUP AND PASSWORD LINK. CONTACT US ON WHATSAPP:08164133799

NOTE 1:- All Text SMS or Whatsapp messages sent to our number 08164133799 are attended to, our phone number Might be Diverted To Avoid Distraction so no need to panic just relax and wait for our confirmation once you subscribe.

NOTE 2:- Ensure to Subscribe A Day Before Each Exam After Payment Relax and Wait For your Pin.

NOTE 3:- PLEASE AVOID CALLING US, NO SENDING OF FAKE MTN CARD. SEND US TEXT MESSAGES OR WHATSAPP MESSAGES ONLY 08164133799

NOTE 4:- NO FREE ANSWERS ON THIS PAGE

RECOMMENDED LINK:

Read Also: How to get Waec Gce Second series Questions and Answers a Midnight before exam

Read Also: 2022 Waec Gce Nov/Dec Examination Timetable.

CLICK HERE TO SEE THE TESTIMONIES OF OUR PREVIOUS WAEC GCE Second series SUBSCRIBERS

Be among Our Yearly Thousands of Successful Candidates this year. Give us a one-time trial and see for yourself!

100% REFUND OF YOUR MONEY IF OUR ANSWERS ARE NOT DELIVERED TO YOUR SATISFACTION.

FOR MORE ENQUIRIES, CONTACT THE ADMIN VIA WHATSAPP:

Chat Mr. Tony K On Whatsapp: 08164133799

Examafrica.com is the No1 verified and trusted exam expo website for Students

2022/2023 waec Gce 2nd Series Nov/Dec General Mathematics Essay And Obj(Objectives) Questions and Answers Expo Runz (Runs)/Dubs/Chokes,2022/2023 waec Gce Mathematics Essay/Theory And Obj(Objectives) Questions and Answers Expo Runz (Runs)/Dubs/Chokes

WAEC GCE 2022/2023 Mathematics Essay And Obj(Objectives) Nov/Dec/External Questions and Answers Expo Runz (Runs)/Dubs/Chokes,Waec Gce 2022/2023 General Mathematics Essay And Obj(Objectives) Nov/Dec/External Questions and Answers Expo Runz (Runs)/Dubs/Chokes

Waec Gce 2022/2023 Mathematics Essay/Theory And Obj(Objectives) Questions and Answers Expo Runz (Runs)/Dubs/Chokes,Waec Gce first 2nd Series Nov/Dec 2022/2023 Mathematics Essay And Obj(Objectives) Nov/Dec/External Questions and Answers Expo Runz (Runs)/Dubs/Chokes

2022/2023 waec gce Mathematics Essay And Obj(Objectives) Questions and Answers Expo Runz (Runs)/Dubs/Chokes,2022/2023 Waec gce Mathematics Questions and Answers Essay and Objectives (obj) expo/Runs/Runz/dubs/Chokes

2022/2023 waec gce Mathematics Essay And Obj(Objectives) Nov/Dec/External Questions and Answers Expo Runz (Runs)/Dubs/Chokes,2022/2023 Waec gce Mathematics Nov/Dec/External Questions and Answers Essay and Objectives (obj) expo/Runs/Runz/dubs/Chokes

Waec gce 2022/2023 Mathematics Essay And Obj(Objectives) Nov/Dec/External Questions and Answers Expo Runz (Runs)/Dubs/Chokes,2022/2023 Waec gce Mathematics November/December/external Questions and Answers Essay and Objectives (obj) expo/Runs/Runz/dubs/Chokes

2022 Waec Gce Mathematics Essay and objectives obj runz expo runs dubs chokes

2022 Waec Gce General Mathematics Essay/theory Essay and obj expo Runz runs dubs chokes

  • 2022 WAEC GCE MATHEMATICS RUNS RUNZ EXPO DUBS CHOKES
  • 2022 WAEC GCE NOV/DEC MATHEMATICS EXPO RUNZ DUBS CHOKES RUNS
  • 2022/2023 WAEC GCE MATHEMATICS NOV/DEC EXAMINATION QUESTIONS AND ANSWERS EXPO/RUNZ/RUNS/DUBS/CHOKES
  • FREE VERIFIED CORRECT ACCURATE BEST LEGIT AUTHENTIC WAEC GCE 2022/2023 NOV/DEC EXTERNAL MATHEMATICS QUESTIONS AND ANSWERS EXPO RUNZ DUBS CHOKES RUNS
  • WAEC GCE 2022/2023 MATHEMATICS NOV/DEC EXAMINATION QUESTIONS AND ANSWERS EXPO/RUNZ/RUNS/DUBS/CHOKES

Be the first to comment

Leave a reply cancel reply.

Your email address will not be published.

Save my name, email, and website in this browser for the next time I comment.

mathematics objective and essay

Copyright © 2024 | Owned and Designed by Mr Tonnyk

itsmyschoollibrary

Your lesson notes in a blink.

NECO ANSWERS , Past Questions & Answer

Protected: 2023 NECO: Mathematics Objectives and Essay Questions with Solutions

mathematics objective and essay

This content is password protected. To view it please enter your password below:

Discover more from itsmyschoollibrary

Subscribe now to keep reading and get access to the full archive.

Type your email…

Continue reading

Your cart is empty

Estimated total.

Rp 10.000 IDR

mathematics objective and essay

Rajacuan69 | Situs Slot Thailand Scatter Hitam Resmi

Couldn't load pickup availability

Dunia perjudian online terus berkembang pesat dengan munculnya berbagai situs yang menawarkan beragam permainan dan pengalaman bagi para pemainnya. Salah satu situs yang kian populer adalah Rajacuan69 , sebuah platform judi daring yang menawarkan berbagai permainan slot Thailand dengan tema Scatter Hitam. Dengan reputasi yang teruji dan berbagai fitur menarik, Rajacuan69 telah menjadi pilihan utama bagi banyak penggemar judi online.

Rajacuan69 adalah salah satu situs judi online terkemuka yang menyediakan permainan slot dengan tema Thailand dan Scatter Hitam . Didirikan dengan komitmen untuk menyajikan pengalaman berjudi yang aman, adil, dan menyenangkan, Rajacuan69 telah berhasil menarik perhatian ribuan pemain dari berbagai belahan dunia.

Kenapa Memilih Rajacuan69?

Ada beberapa alasan mengapa Rajacuan69 menjadi pilihan favorit bagi para pemain judi online:

  • Kepuasan Pelanggan: Rajacuan69 menempatkan kepuasan pelanggan sebagai prioritas utama. Mereka menawarkan layanan pelanggan yang responsif dan ramah, siap membantu para pemain dengan berbagai pertanyaan dan masalah yang mungkin timbul.
  • Beragam Permainan: Situs ini menawarkan berbagai macam permainan slot Thailand dengan tema Scatter Hitam yang menarik. Dari klasik hingga yang paling inovatif, pemain dapat memilih permainan sesuai dengan selera dan preferensi mereka.
  • Keamanan dan Kepercayaan: Rajacuan69 memprioritaskan keamanan dan kepercayaan. Mereka menggunakan teknologi enkripsi canggih untuk melindungi data pribadi dan keuangan para pemain, sehingga Anda dapat bermain dengan aman tanpa khawatir tentang privasi Anda.
  • Promosi dan Bonus: Situs ini juga dikenal dengan berbagai promosi dan bonus yang menarik. Mulai dari bonus selamat datang hingga program loyalitas, Rajacuan69 memberikan insentif tambahan kepada para pemain untuk tetap setia dan aktif.
  • Aksesibilitas: Rajacuan69 dapat diakses melalui berbagai platform, termasuk desktop dan perangkat seluler. Ini memungkinkan para pemain untuk berjudi kapan saja dan di mana saja sesuai dengan kenyamanan mereka.

Rajacuan69 adalah pilihan yang sempurna bagi para pecinta judi online yang mencari pengalaman berjudi yang menyenangkan dan mengasyikkan. Dengan berbagai permainan slot Thailand yang menarik, layanan pelanggan yang prima, keamanan yang terjamin, dan bonus yang melimpah, Rajacuan69 terus menarik minat pemain dari seluruh dunia. Jika Anda mencari situs judi online yang dapat diandalkan dan menghibur, Rajacuan69 adalah jawabannya. Jangan ragu untuk bergabung dan rasakan sensasi kemenangan di tangan Anda!

RAJACUAN69

Daftar Sekarang!

  • Choosing a selection results in a full page refresh.
  • Opens in a new window.

2022-2023 WAEC Mathematics Questions: Essay and Objectives with ANSWERS for easy go

2022-2023 WAEC Mathematics Questions: Essay and Objectives with ANSWERS for easy go

2022-2023 WAEC Mathematics Questions: Essay and Objectives with ANSWERS for easy go – Do you understand mathematics? Is it possible for you to improve on your knowledge of mathematics? So, here are WAEC Mathematics questions and answers. Other references are for WAEC mathematics syllabus 2022/2023, past questions on mathematics and WAEC mathematics expo 2022. So, are you a WAEC candidate? If your answer is yes, this post will show you the WAEC Mathematics answers and the tricks you need to excel in your WAEC exams. Just read on.

Table of Contents

As a matter of fact, the above keywords are searched by WAEC candidates on google. Here I will show you WAEC Mathematics questions and answers. Just read on.

0.1 GENERAL MATHEMATICS/MATHEMATICS (CORE) 1 0.2 2021/2022 WAEC Mathematics Questions and Answers 0.3 Solutions to WAEC Mathematics Questions 1 WAEC Maths Essay and Objective 2021 (EXPO) GENERAL MATHEMATICS/MATHEMATICS (CORE) 1 OBJECTIVE TEST

2021/2022 WAEC Mathematics Questions and Answers Symbols used:

^ means raise to power / division

SQRT means square root

Scroll to the bottom to get the 2021 WAEC answers and refresh the page

Solutions to WAEC Mathematics Questions

1.Evaluate: (0.064)^-1/3

2.Solve: y+1/2 – 2y-1/3 = 4

3.Simplify, correct to three significant figures, (27.63)^2 – (12.37)^2

4.If 7 + y = 4 (mod 8), find the least value of y, 10<=y<=30

5.If T = (prime numbers) and M = (odd numbers) are subsets of U = (x: 0<x<=10, and x is an integer), find (T’ n M’).

A. (4, 6, 8, 10)

B. (1, 4, 6, 8, 10)

C. (1, 2, 4, 6, 8, 10)

D. (1, 2, 3, 5, 7, 8, 9)

6.Evaluate: log9 base 3 – log8 base 2 /log9 base 3

7.If 23y = 1111two, find the value of y.

See further maths here

8.How many students scored above the mean score?

  • If 6, P and 14 are consecutive terms in an Arithmetic Progression (A.P), find the value of P.
  • Evaluate: 2 (SQRT 28) – 3 (SQRT 50) + (SQRT 50)

A. 4 (SQRT 7) – 21 (SQRT 2)

B. 4 (SQRT 7) – 11 (SQRT 2)

C. 4 (SQRT 7) – 9 (SQRT 2)

D. 4 (SQRT 7) + (SQRT 2)

  • If m : n = 2 : 1, evaluate 3m^2 – 2n^2 /m^2 + mn
  • H varies directly as p and inversely as the square of y. If H = 1, p = 8 and y = 2, find H in terms of p and y

A. H = p /4y^2

B. H = 2p / y^2

C. H = p / 2 y^2

D. H = p / y^2

  • Solve 4x^2 – 16x + 15

A. X = 1 (1/2) or X = -2 (1/2)

B. X = 1 (1/2) or X = 2 (1/2)

C. X = 1 (1/2) or X = -1 (1/2)

D. X = -1 (1/2) or X = -2 (1/2)

  • Evaluate 0.42 divided by 2.5 /0.5 x 2.05, leaving the answer in standard form.

A. 1.639 x 10^2

B. 1.639 x 10^1

C. 1.639 x 10^-1

D. 1.639 x 10^-2

  • Simplify: log6 – 3log3 + 2/3log27.
  • Bala sold an article for 6,900.00 naira and made a profit of 15 percent. Calculate his percentage profit if he had sold for 6600.00.

A. 5 percent

B. 10 percent

C. 12 percent

D. 13 percent

  • If 3p = 4q and 9p = 8q-12, find the value of pq.
  • If (0.25)^y = 32, find the value of y.

A. y = -5/2

B. y = -3/2

  • Simplify: x^2 – 5x – 14 / x^2 – 9x + 14

A. X – 7 /x + 7

B. X + 7 /x – 7

C. X – 2 /x + 4

D. X + 2 /x – 2

  • Which of these values would make 3p – 1 /p^2 – p undefined?

past qts and Answers for mathematics click here

  • The total surface area of a solid cylinder is 165 cm2. If the base diameter is 7 cm, calculate its height. (Take pi = 22/7)
  • If 2^a = SQRT(64) and b/a = 3, evaluate a^2 + b^2.
  • In triangle XYZ, line XZ = 32 cm, angle YXZ = 52 degrees and XZY = 90 degrees. Find, correct to the nearest centimeter, line XZ.
  • If log 2 base x = 0.3, evaluate log 8 base x.
  • An arc subtends an angle of 72 degrees at the centre of a circle. Find the length of the arc if the radius of the circle is 3.5 cm. (Take pi = 22/7)
  • Make b the subject of the relation

lb = 1/2(a+b)h

A. ah /2l – h

B. 2l – h/al

C. al/2l – h

D. al/2 – h

28.Express, correct to three significant figures, 0.003597.

Past English qts and Ans click here

  • Eric sold his house through an agent who charged 8 percent commission on the selling price. If Eric received 117,760.00 dollars after the sale, what was the selling price of the house?

A. 130,000.00 dollars

B. 128,000.00 dollars

C. 125,000.000 dollars

D. 120,000.00 dollars

  • A rectangular board has a length of 15 cm and width x cm. If its sides are doubled, find its new area.

A. 60x cm squared

B. 45x cm squared

C. 30x cm squared

D. 15x cm squared

  • In the diagram, POS and ROT are straight lines. OPQR is a parallelogram, line OS = line OT and angle OST = 50 degrees. Calculate the value of angle OPQ.

A. 100 degrees

B. 120 degrees

C.140 degrees

D. 160 degrees

  • Factorize completely: (2x + 2y)(x-y) + (2x – 2y)(x + y)

A. 4(x – y)(x + y)

B. 4(x – y)

C. 2(x – y) (x + y)

D. 2(x – y)

2022-2023 WAEC Mathematics Questions: Essay and Objectives with ANSWERS for easy go

  • The interior angles of a polygon are 3x, 2x, 4x, 3x and 6x. Find the size of the smallest angle of the polygon.

A. 80 degrees

B. 60 degrees

C. 40 degrees

D. 30 degrees

  • A box contains 2 white and 3 blue identical balls. If two balls are picked at random from the box, one after the other with replacement, what is the probability that they are of different colours?
  • Find the equation of a straight line passing through the points (1, -5) and having gradient of ¾.

A. 3x + 4y – 23 = 0

B. 3x + 4y + 23 = 0

C. 3x – 4y + 23 = 0

D. 3x – 4y – 23 = 0

  • The foot of a ladder is 6 m from the base of an electric pole. The top of the ladder rest against the pole at a point 8 m above the ground. How long is the ladder?
  • If tan x = 3/4, 0<x<90,

evaluate cos x/2sin x

  • From the top of a vertical cliff 20 m high, a boat at sea can be sighted 75 m away and on the same horizontal position as the foot of the cliff. Calculate, correct to the nearest degree, the angle of depression of the boat from the top of the cliff.

A. 56 degrees

B. 75 degrees

C. 16 degrees

D. 15 degrees

  • In the diagram, O is the centre of the circle of radius 18 cm. If angle ZXY = 70 degrees, calculate the length of arc ZY. (Take pi = 22/7)

In the diagram, RT is tangent to the circle at R, angle PQR = 70 degrees, angle QRT = 52 degrees, angle QSR = y and angle PRQ = x. Use the diagram to answer questions 40 and 41

  • Find the value of y.

A. 70 degrees

B. 60 degree

C. 52 degree

D. 18 degree

  • Calculate the value of x

B. 58 degrees

C. 55 degrees

D. 48 degrees

  • Calculate the variance of 2, 4, 7, 8, 9
  • The fourth term of an Arithmetic Progression (A.P.) is 37 and the first term is -20. Find the common difference.

See Financial Accounting qts and Ans here

In the diagram, PQ is parallel to RS, angle QFG = 105 degrees and angle FEG = 50 degrees. Use the diagram to answer questions 44 and 45.

  • Find the value of m

A. 130 degrees

B. 105 degrees

C. 75 degrees

D. 55 degrees

  • Find the values of n

A. 40 degrees

B. 55 degrees

D. 130 degrees

  • A box contains 5 red, 6 green and 7 yellow pencils of the same size. What is the probability of picking a green pencil at random?
  • The pie chart represents fruits on display in a grocery shop. If there are 60 oranges on display, how many apples are there?

The following are scores obtained by some students in a test.

8 18 10 14 18 11 13 14 17 15 8 16 13

Use this information to answer questions 48 to 50

  • Find the mode of the distribution
  • Find the median score.

50.There are 8 boys and 4 girls in a lift. What is the probability that the first person who steps out of the lift will be a boy?

If you want to boost your business with funding, click here

  • Financial Accounting Past Questions & Answers
  • Further Maths Past Questions & Answers
  • Latest Secondary Education updates
  • Physics 2021 WAEC Questions & Answers
  • English Language for WAEC May/ June 2021
  • How to become a professional
  • Economics Questions for 2021/2022
  • Commerce Question & Answers WAEC 2021/2022
  • Chemistry Questions for 2021/2022 WAEC
  • Secondary Education List of Subjects – WAEC approved
  • Tips for Successful Professionals
  • Tertiary Education updates
  • Latest professional tips
  • How the basic primary education works
  • Professionals and Recruitment

Good for reading through. I know that this post has actually equipped you for your forth coming Maths WAEC exams.

Finally if you have further questions, please drops your phone numbers in our comment box below. You can also bookmark this page for further review. Please share to reach your friends. Do follow us on the Facebook handle, please. And now, for your inspirations click here , and then for your entrepreneurial challenges, click here.

Leave a Reply Cancel reply

Your email address will not be published. Required fields are marked *

Save my name, email, and website in this browser for the next time I comment.

  • Career & Training
  • Career Guide
  • Loans & Grants
  • Online Programs
  • Professional Tips
  • Real Estate
  • Scholarship
  • Travel Visas
  • Terms and Conditions

Noniwap

EACH PAPER ==> N1000 MTN TO:  09033919669

WAEC Further Mathematics 2023 Questions and Answer Obj and Theory

WAEC Further Mathematics Questions and Answers are no cost for all Weac candidates in Ghana, Liberia, Nigeria, Sierra Leone, and The Gambia. This page contains all Waec Further Mathematics questions and answers for 2023 as well as the most frequently asked questions are posted here.

Waec Candidates who registered for the West African Examination Council (WAEC) SSCE Examination will write their Waec Further Mathematics For general students. All the information you require to you to succeed and pass the 2023 WAEC Exam will be provided and you must take the time to read it all.

Table of Contents

2023 Waec Further Mathematics Exam Papers

2023 Waec Further Mathematics Exam Papers Are

  • Waec Further Mathematics Essay Questions
  • Waec Further Mathematics Objectives Questions,

You will be writing two papers in a single day. In this article the previous year’s Waec questions and the correct answers for Further Mathematics are released and the 2023 Waec Further Maths Exam Questions will also be made available to those who will be taking part in the 2023 Waec exam.

Further Mathematics/Mathematics (Elective) 2 (Essay) – 09:30am – 12:00pm Further Mathematics/Mathematics (Elective) 1 (Objective) – 3:00pm – 4:30pm

F/Maths OBJ: 1-10: BBCCCDDCDB 11-20: BBBBBADDBA 21-30: ACCDABDBAA 31-40: ACDDADDDBD

NO.1, 2, 3, 4, 5, 6, 7, 8, 10, 11, 14 COMPLETED

mathematics objective and essay

Answers Loading…

QUESTIONS: ????

mathematics objective and essay

2023 Waec Further Mathematics Questions and Answers Objective Questions (paper 1)

The 2023 WEC Further Maths questions and answers are loading! 2023 Further Maths objective solutions Loading! 2023 Further Mathematics Theory Answers Loading!!! Bookmark the website to check for answers to be released. Better still, refresh the site to determine whether the answers to 2023 Waec Further Mathematics questions and answers have changed.

SUBSCRIPTION PRICE

== whatsapp:: # 1000 mtn card.

WhatsApp MEANS all answers (theory & obj) will be sent to you on whatsapp.

== Online PIN:: # 500 MTN CARD

Online PIN MEANS The Pin to access our answers online via  www.noniexpo.com  will be sent to u at least 2hours before the exam to access our answers

CLICK HERE TO JOIN OUR TELEGRAM CHANNEL FOR ALL 2023 EXAM ANSWERS FOR FREE

Send the following details:-, (i) mtn card pin(s) (ii) your name (iii) subject (iv) phone number ===> 09033919669 via sms.

You will receive your PIN immediately after we have confirmed your payment.

BELOW IS OUR PREVIOUS ANSWERS 2023

mathematics objective and essay

WAEC FURTHER MATHS Answers 2023

WAEC FURTHER MATHS 2023 theory Answers, WAEC 2023 FURTHER MATHS Questions, 2023 WAEC FURTHER MATHS Questions And Answers, Free WAEC FURTHER MATHS 2023 Expo Answer Runs, WAEC 2023 FURTHER MATHS June/July Expo, WAEC 2023/2023 FURTHER MATHS Specimen for free, 2023/2023 WAEC FURTHER MATHS Questions And Answers, Correct WAEC 2023 FURTHER MATHS Answers, Verified WAEC 2023 FURTHER MATHS Questions And Answers

WAEC FURTHER MATHS 2023

WAEC 2023 FURTHER MATHS expo, 2023 WAEC FURTHER MATHS answers, 2023 WAEC FURTHER MATHS runs, 2023 WAEC FURTHER MATHS questions, WAEC ssce 2023 FURTHER MATHS expo answers, WAEC 2023 FURTHER MATHS objective and essay Expo answers now available, July FURTHER MATHS theory Answers for 2023, FURTHER MATHS Questions WAEC Ssce Expo Answers Here, Free WAEC FURTHER MATHS correct Expo 2023 answers Runz WAEC FURTHER MATHS, WAEC Ssce 2023 Free FURTHER MATHS Questions and Answers Expo for WAEC

F/Maths OBJ: 1-10: CABCBABCAB 11-20: DCBADBDCCB 21-30: CAADCCDCCC 31-40: CDBCBCBBCC

mathematics objective and essay

CHECK OUR PREVIOUS EXAMS BELOW:

ACCOUNTING OBJ: 1-10: CDCABACACC 11-20: ABACBADDCB 21-30: CBCABDACBD 31-40: BABAACCDAC 41-50: DCDCCCBBDA

INSTRUCTIONS: YOU’RE TO ANSWER TWO(2) QUESTIONS FROM SECTION A, AND THREE(3) FROM SECTION B

mathematics objective and essay

(3ai) Entrance Fees or Admission Fees is the amount that a person pays at the time of becoming a member of a Not-for-Profit Organization. It is a revenue receipt. Therefore, we account it as an income and credit it to Income and Expenditure Account.

(3aii) A subscription is a signed agreement between a supplier and customer that the customer will receive and provide payment for regular products or services, usually for a one-year period.

(3b) (Pick Any five) (i) No Opening Balance:- Opening balance is not require to prepare income and expenditure account.

(ii) Accrual Basis:- Income and expenditure account is maintained on accrual basis.

(iii) Based On Receipt And Payment Account:- Income and expenditure account is prepared on the basis of receipt and payment account at the end of the accounting year.

(iv) Non-cash Items:- This account records non-cash items also (v) Debit And Credit Rule:- Expenses and losses are debited and incomes are credited as it is a nominal account.

(vi) No Capital Transactions:- Only revenue items are included in income and expenditure account. So, capital items are excluded while preparing this account.

(vii) Only Current Year’s Transactions:- Income and expenditure account includes only current periods transactions.

(1a) Accounting concepts are a set of general conventions that can be used as guidelines when dealing with accounting situations.

(1b) (I) Business Entity: The business entity concept states that the transactions associated with a business must be separately recorded from those of its owners or other businesses.

(II) Accrual: The accrual principle is an accounting concept that requires transactions to be recorded in the time period in which they occur, regardless of when the actual cash flows for the transaction are received.

(III) Going concern: is an accounting term for a company that is financially stable enough to meet its obligations and continue its business for the foreseeable future.

(IV) Consistency: The concept of consistency means that accounting methods once adopted must be applied consistently in future

(V) Periodicity: The periodicity concept is a period during which business enterprises are required to prepare financial statement at specified intervals.

(VI) Historical cost: A historical cost is a measure of value used in accounting in which the value of an asset on the balance sheet is recorded at its original cost when acquired by the company.

(4a) Bank reconciliation statement is a summary of banking and business activity that reconciles an entity’s bank account with its financial records. In other words the statement outlines the deposits, withdrawals, and other activities affecting a bank account for a specific period.

(4bi) Bank charges covers all charges and fees made by a bank to their customers. In common parlance, the term often relates to charges in respect of personal current accounts or checking account.

(4bii) Standing order is an instruction a bank account holder gives to their bank to pay a set amount at regular intervals to another’s account. The instruction is sometimes known as a banker’s order.

(4biii) Credit transfer” means a payment transaction by which a credit institution transfers funds to a payee’s account on the basis of a payer’s order, and the payer and the payee can be the same person.

(4biv) Dishonoured cheques are cheques that a bank on which is drawn declines to pay. There are a number of reasons why a bank would refuse to honour a cheque, with non-sufficient funds being the most common one, indicating that there are insufficient cleared funds in the account on which the cheque was drawn.

(4bv) Unpresented cheque simply means that a cheque has been written and accounted for, but it has not yet been paid out by the bank from which the money is being drawn. Unpresented cheques are also referred to as outstanding cheques because the funds in question are, as the name suggests, outstanding.

(4bvi) Uncredited cheques represent money that is available to the company but has not yet been recognised by the bank. This comes in the form of cheques paid in by customers and clients.

mathematics objective and essay

CIVIC OBJ: 1-10: BCDDCDCBCA 11-20: AACCCACDAA 21-30: CDBDACCCAA 31-40: ABBCABBCBD 41-50: DBDABDCCDD

(4a) Secret cult is an enclosed organized association or group of people devoted to the same cause. It is also referred to as a dangerous and deadly group that share common ideologies, believe in secret, esoteric, mystic and engage in violent practices. Members if the cult groups commit themselves to oath allegiance, which serves as their strong bond.

(4b) (i)Public campaign against cultism: Different organizations, including the government, schools, religious institutions, and parents, should promote awareness against cultism. Seminars and workshops should be organized to discuss the dangers of cultism all over schools without leaving out the primary schools.

(ii)Government Standard: The government should also make laws to punish cultists for pushing away students and young people from joining these groups. The political leaders supporting them should also be put to judgment because they are damaging other children’s lives to make theirs better;

(iii)Discipline and Studying hard in school to achieve success: Students should be kept busy and engage in school via curricular and extra curricular activities. Because it is a known fact that an “idle mind is the devil’s workshop”. When students are engage with hard work, they will not have time to join cult.

(iv)Moral Education should be made compulsory in the primary and secondary schools in the country.Parents should take time to understand their children, give enough time to listen to them at home and satisfy their emotional psychological and physical needs.

============================

(7ai) Civil society organization: Civil society organization are groups of people who came together to pursue a common cause or goal and equally provide an alternative to pressure groups in many areas like politics,human right matters etc. They are non-governmental organization (NGOs) who are defenders of laws,fundamental rights,justices and good governance.

(7aii) Free and independent press: The press is one of the vital institutions in the practice of government and also a major pillar of true democracy. No democracy exists without free press. The press can be described as the total sum of all the organization and systems that make up the mass media of any given society. The press or mass media includes all agents of public opinion and the watch dog that speaks through the voice or by pen.

(7aiii) Political party: Political party is an organization of citizens who act together as a political unit,having distinctive aims and objectives involving political questions in the state and acting together and seeking to obtain controls of government. Political parties are usually the institutions involved in the electoral contests. They exist in order to contest elections or bring about a condition that will lead to election of people’s representatives to legislative and executive councils.

(7b) (i) Anti Party activities: some party members are disloyal and involved in anti party activities which will lead to competition among each party

(ii)Irresponsible acts: Most of the party leaders are irresponsible. Many of them were imposed on party members or faithfuls. Irresponsible acts lead to division and competition among parties.

(iii)corruption and favouritism: Political parties are always guilty of nepotism ,bribery and corruption. Corruption and favouritism is one of the major cause of competition among parties

===============================

(6a) Youth empowerment is an idea or programmes fashioned to enable the youth learn skills,trade or profession . it is inherent in the idea of training and education. Youth empowerment aims at laying a solid foundation for sustainable poverty reduction ,employment generation, wealth creation and value orientation.

(6b) (i) Life Coping Skills: These are natural skills which every organism including man, acquires from birth to adapt fittingly in his or its environment. They are survival Instincts or skills.

(ii) Manipulative Skills: These skills are seen in skills acquisition centres as it involves economic activities that inculcate skills such as technical education.

(iii) Intellectual Skills: These skills are coordinates in character. It is the literary or theoretical frameworks that guide the practical aspects of the works, economic and scientific undertakings

(iv) Communicative Skills: Communication is a very important aspect of our life. Man evolved communications skills as a social being to enable him pass or send information from one person to the other or from place to place.

(v) Artistic Skills: These are close to communicative skills and are more complex. Includes they art of good writing, fine and applied arts, music and drama. These skills make effective use of all the other four kinds of skills where necessary.

(vi)Decision-making skills; These can be the difference in making a choice that improves your organization. The aptitude to make decisions is a leadership trait, which portrays your ability to think objectively and relates concepts to the goals you’re trying to reach.

===================================

(2a) (i)Right to life: Life is the greatest gift of God. We must do our best to protect our lives and while we do this, we must not do things that will destroy other people’s lives of put them in danger.

(ii)Freedom of speech: The UDHR declare that human beings have the right to speak their minds or express their opinion without dear of being intimidated or punished.

(iii)Freedom of Assembly: We all have the right to gather together with out friends and gold meeting in any place of our choice . Nobody can force us to join any group against our will.

(iv)Freedom from fear: We all have the right to be protected by the law and have the right to live as citizen of our country without fear

(v)Freedom from Want: The basic of man should be provided by out various government. Those needs are food, clothing and shelter. This is why the UDHR has listed it as one of the core freedom.

(vi)Freedom from discrimination: Everyone is entitled to all the Right and freedoms in the UDHR. Nobody should be discriminated against because of race, sex, religion, color, language, birth etc.

(vii)Freedom of movement: We all have the right to move about freely in our country and to go where we want to go without being harassed. If the government imposes curfew, it limits your freedom of movement.

(2b) (i)Study and know your Fundamental Human Rights and the Articles of the UDHR: You cannot claim Rights if you do not know that they exist and you cannot immediately quote them when the need arises. Ignorance is the greatest challenge to the UDHR.

(ii)Individuals who know their Rights must help Teach Others: Do not keep the knowledge to yourself alone. You must be ready to alert other people when their Fundamental Human Rights have been violated and teach them what to do to seek redress. You can do this when discussing with friends in your school

(iii)Groups can channel Advocacy through the print and Electronic media: Each Human rights group should have a website where they can be reached easily . they can publish abuses of human rights and their recommendations in newspaper,magazines and journals. They can also speak put through the radio and television

(iv)Groups can organize a forum from Time to Time and Educate people on human right: They can organize lectures on good governance and how government can help to promote and preserve human rights. In Nigeria a group known as human right watch has devoted much energy ,time and resources to educate people on the need for preservation of human right and championing the cause of the helpless.

(8a) Modern mode of popular participation is the mode of popular participation carried out through expressing of oneself through the mass media.

(8b) [Pick Any SiX] (i) Legitimacy of elected governments: If citizens actively participate in electoral process, society will have an elected legitimate government. (ii) National development: There will be rapid socio-economic development if citizens participate in the electoral or political process. (iii) Political stability: This ensures law and order for economic and political development in the society. (iv) Responsible and responsive government: The society will elect or get a government that is receptive to the people’s concerns, needs and aspirations. (v) Political awareness: When citizens participate in the electoral/political process, they will become politically conscious, enjoy their rights and perform corresponding duties and obligations to the society. (vi) Credible elections: When citizens actively participate in the electoral or political process it will confer credibility on the process. (vii) Peaceful order of succession: Peaceful transition is ensured from one regime to another. (viii) Peace and harmony: When citizens actively participate in the political process they will enjoy peace and harmony without much agitation. (ix) Accountability, transparency, due process and probity: Active participation of citizens in the political process ensures accountability, transparency, due process and probity in governance for the common good of the society.

mathematics objective and essay

Waec Further Maths 2023 Answers

Waec further maths answers 2023, waec further maths 2023.

Waec Further Maths 2023 Answers, Waec 2023 Further Maths Questions, 2023 Waec Further Maths Questions And Answers, Free Waec Further Maths 2023 Expo Answer Runs, Waec 2023 Further Maths June/July Expo, Waec 2023/2023 Further Maths Specimen for free, 2023/2023 Waec Further Maths Questions And Answers, Correct Waec 2023 Further Maths Answers, Verified Waec 2023 Further Maths Questions And Answers

Waec 2023 Further Maths expo, 2023 Waec Further Maths answers, 2023 Waec Further Maths runs, 2023 Waec Further Maths questions, Waec ssce 2023 Further Maths expo answers, Waec 2023 Further Maths objective and essay Expo answers now available, July Further Maths theory Answers for 2023, Further Maths Questions Waec Ssce Expo Answers Here, Free Waec Further Maths correct Expo 2023 answers Runz Waec Further Maths, Waec Ssce 2023 Free Further Maths essay Questions and Answers Expo for Waec Further Maths Paper 1 and Paper 2 Questions and Answers Expo Now Posted

Share this Post:

You may also like.

waec 2023

WAEC ANIMAL HUSBANDRY ANSWERS 2024

Waec 2024 runs – click here to subscribe.

mathematics objective and essay

NOUN Matriculation Gown Collection Notice for Freshers

Waec timetable for science student 2024.

yaba

Level Up Your Career: Apply Now for the FUOYE-YABATECH Degree...

WAEC QUESTION AND ANSWERS 2023

WAEC 2024 RUNS [MIDNIGHT ANSWERS]

About the author.

' src=

The loyal guy from another planet, Whom always get what he always asked for. || Professional Blogger || The Main Man Behind Noniwap.com concept.

I SUPPORT YOU

Leave a Comment X

Join NONIEXPO Telegram Channel For All Exam Answers

Get the Most Legit Information and Guide on the Latest Jobs in Nigeria, Facebook and Education Here

WAEC GCE Mathematics Questions and Answers for 2023/2024 (Theory and Objectives)

WAEC GCE Mathematics questions and answers 2023 .  Welcome to 2023 WAEC Mathematics Questions and Answers. You will find WAEC GCE Mathematics Objective Answers, WAEC Mathematics Essay 2023, WAEC GCE 2023 Mathematics, and the tips you need to pass your WAEC GCE Mathematics examination with ease.

WAEC GCE Mathematics Essay and Objectives Questions and Answers (Expo)

The 2023 WAEC GCE Mathematics expo will be posted on this page during the WAEC GCE Mathematics examination. Keep checking and refreshing this page for the answers.

WAEC GCE Nov/Dec Mathematics Questions and Answers 2023 Loading…

GCE Maths OBJ Loading…

————————————————————————————-

Note: The answers below are the 2020 Nov/Dec answers.

1-10: BDBBBDCDCC 11-20: AACCADA-AA 21-30: DDBDADADAD 31-40: AABAADCCDC 41-50: CCBDAABACD

More Answers Loading… Keep reloading this page

——————————————————————————————————-

These questions below are for practice.

1. Simplify:​​ √108 108 ​​ +√125125​​ ­-​​ √75.75.

(a) √33​​ +​​ 5√555​​ ​​

 (b).​​ 6√36√3​​ -​​ 5√555​​

 (c)​​ 6√36√3​​ +​​ √22​​ 

(d).​​ 6√36√3​​ -​​ √22​​ 

2. Evaluate:​​ (64^1/2+ 125^1/3)64^1/2+ 125^1/3

3. Given that​​  y ​​ varies inversely as the square of​​  x. ​​ if​​  x =3 when​​  y =100, find the equation connecting ​​  x ​​ and​​  y

(a) yx 2 =300

(b).​​  yx 2 =900

(c)​​  yx 2 =100x9100x9​​ 

(d) y = 900x 2  ​​​​ 

4. Find the value of​​ x for which 32 four ​​ = 22 base x

5. Simplify:​​ 2 whole number1/4 x 3 whole number1/2 ÷4 whole number3/8

(a).​​ 5/9 

 ​​ (b)​​ 1 whole number1/5​​ 

(c)​​ 1 whole number 1/4​​ 

(d)​​ 1 whole number 4/5

6. There are 250 boys and 150 girls in a school. If 60% of the boys and 40% of the girls play football. What percentage of the school play football?

7. If log 10 ​​ (6 x−4) x-4)​​ – log 10 ​​ 2=1, solve for​​ xx

8. If F =​​ 9C/5+ 32, find C when F = 98.6

9. If​​ y ÷​​ 2 x ​​ = 4 and​​ y−3x=−1, ​​ find the value of (x+y)

10. If​​ x:y:z=2:3:4,​​ Evaluate​​ 9x+3y/6z−2y

(a)1 whole number1/2​​ 

(b)​​ 2

(c)​​ ​​ 2 whole number1/2​​ 

(d)​​ 3

11. Simplify:​​ 2−18m^2/1+3m

(a) 2(1+3m)

(b) 2(2+3m 2 )

(c) 2(1-3m)

(d) 2(1-3m 2 )

12. A curve is such that when​​  y = 0,​​ x​​ = -2 or​​ x=3. Find the equation for the curve.

(a).​​ y=  x^2-5 x -6

(b).​​ y= x^2+5x−6 

 (c)​​ y= x2+x−6  

 (d)​​ y=x^2-  x-6

13. The volume of a cylindrical tank, 10m high is 385m 3 . Find the diameter of the tank. Take​​ π=22/7

(a). 14 m  

(b). 10 m  

(c). 7 m

 ​​ (d). 5 m 

(a)113 cm^3  

 ​​ (b)​​ 131cm^3 

(c)​​ 311cm^3

 (d)​​ 414cm^3

15. A piece of thread of length 21.4cm is used to form a sector of a circle of radius 4.2cm on a piece of cloth. Calculate, correct to the nearest degree, the angle of the sector.​​ Take​​ π=22/7

(a) 170 0 ​​ 

(b) 177 0 ​​ 

(c) 182 0 ​​ 

(d) 192 0 ​​

waec mathematics

In the diagram which of the following ratios is​​ equal to​​ ∣PN∣ / ∣PQ∣

(a) ∣PN∣/ ∣PR∣​​

 (b).​​ ∣PM∣/∣PQ∣

​​ (c)​​∣PM∣/∣PR∣

​​ (d)​​ ∣PR/ ∣PQ∣

waec mathematics past questions and answers

In the diagram​​  PS ​​ and​​  RS ​​ are tangents to the circle centre O,​​  <PSR ​​ = 70 0 ,​​  <POR ​​ = m and​​  <PQR ​​ = n. Find (m+n).

(a) 110 0 ​​ 

(b) 135 0 ​​ 

(c) 165 0 ​​

 (d) 225 0

​​ 18.

may/june waec mathematics

Find the value of t in the diagram

(a) 63 0 ​​ 

(b) 117 0 ​​

 (c) 126 0 ​​

 (d) 234 0 ​​ 

​​ 19.

waec maths question and answers

In the diagram,​​  PR​​  is a tangent to the circle at Q, QT//RS,​​  < SQR = 35 0 ​​ and​​  < RSQ = 50 0 . Find the value of​​  <QST.

(a) 40 0 ​​

 (b) 65 0 ​​ 

(c) 85​​ 

(d) 95 0 ​​ 

20. The angles of a polygon are​​ x, 2 x , 2 x,  (x-30 0 ), (x-20 0 ) and (x-10 0 ). Find the value of​​ x.

(a) 45 0​​ 

(b) 84 0 ​​ 

(c) 85 0 ​​ 

21. If​​  M​​  ​​ and​​  N ​​ are the points (-3, 8) and (5, -7) respectively, find​​ |MN|.

(a) 8 units

(b) 11 units

(c) 15 units

(d) 17 units​​ 

22. The equation of the line through the points (4, 2) and (-8, -2) is​​ 3y​​ = p  x​​ +​​  q , where​​ pp​ and​​ q​​ are constants. Find the value of​​ p.

Recommended: WAEC GCE Physics Questions and Answers

23. The angle of elevation of the top of a tree from a point 27 m​​ away and on the same horizontal ground as the foot of the tree is 30 0 . Find the height of the tree.

(a) 27 m ​​

 (b) 13.5√3 m​​

 (c)​​ 13.5√2 m 

(d)​​ 9√3 m

24. If tan​​ x=4/3, 0 0​​  < x<90 0 , find the value of sin​​ x​​ – cos x .

 (b)​​ 1/5​​ 

(c)​​ 5/12​​ 

(d)​​ 1 whole number 2 /5

25. Given that​​ Y​​ is 20​​ m​​ on a bearing of 300 0 ​​ from​​ X, how far south of​​ Y​​ is​​ X?

(a) 10 m ​​

 (b) 15 m 

​​ (c) 25 m ​​

 (d) 30 m 

26. The mean of 1,3,5,7 and​​ x​​ is 4. Find the value of​​ .x.

27. Find the median of 2,1,0,3,1,14,0,1 and 2.

The table shows the distributions of goals scored by​​ 25 teams in a football competition. Use it to answer questions 28 and 29.

28. Calculate the probability that a team​​ selected at random scored at most 3 goals.

(c)​​ 6/25​​

 (d)​​ 2/5 

29. Find the probability that a team selected at random scored either 4 or 7 goals.

(a) 9/25 ​​

 (b)​​ 11/25 ​​ 

(c)​​ 3/5 ​​

 (d)​​ 18/25

In the diagram, WXYZ, is a rectangle with dimension 8cm by 6cm,​​  P ,​​  Q ,​​  R ​​ and S are the midpoints of the sides of the rectangle as shown. Use this information to answer questions​​  30 ​​ and​​  31 .

Waec mathematics questions and answers

30. What type of quadrilateral is the shaded region?

(a)Trapezium

(b)​​ Prism

(c) Rectangle

(d) Rhombus

31. Calculate the area of the part of the rectangle that is​​  not shaded.​​ 

(a) 25​​ cm^2​​ 

(b) 24 cm^2 ​​

 (c) 16 cm^2 ​​ 

(d)​​ 12 cm^2 

32. The​​ total surface area of a hemisphere is 75πcm^2. Find its radius

(a) 5.0 cm ​​ 

(b) 7.0​​ cm​​ 

(c) 8.5​​ cm​​ 

(d)​​ 12.0 cm 

33. Find the values of​​ x​​ for which​​ x−5/x(x−1)​​ is​​ 

(b) -5 or 5

(c) -1 or 5

34. Solve the equation 2 x 2 ​​ – x-6=0.

(a) x=−3/2​​ or 2

(b)​​ x=−2 or 3/2​​ 

(c)​​ x=−3 or 2 

(d)​​ x=3 or−2

35. Factorize completely the expression (x+2) 2 ​​ – (2 x+1) 2

(a) (3  x+2)(1- xx)​​ 

(b) (3  x+2)(1-  x)​​

 (c) (3 x+2) 2 ​​ 

(d) 3( x+1)(1- x)

36. Find the n th​​  term of the sequence 2 x 3, 4 x 6

(a) 2 n ​​ x 3(n + 1)

(b) 2 n ​​ x 3n

(c) 2 n ​​ x 3 n  ​​​​ 

(d) 2 n ​​ x 3 n-1

37. If 3x​​ = 4 (mod 5), find the least value of​​ xx

38. The solution of​​ x​​ + 2​​ ≥​​ 2 x ​​ + 1 is illustrated on the number line as

39. If​​  p ​​ and​​  q ​​ are two statements, under what condition would​​  p ​​ –​​  q ​​ be​​  false ?

(a) If​​  p​​  is true and​​  q ​​ is true

(b) If​​  p ​​ is true and​​  q ​​ is false

(c) If​​  p ​​ is false and​​  q ​​ is false

(d) If​​  p ​​ is false and​​  q ​​ is true​​ 

waec mathematics questions and answers

The diagram shows a trapezium inscribed in a​​ semi-circle. If O is mid-point of WZ and​​ |WX| =​​ |XY|​​ =​​ |YZ|, calculate the value of​​ m.m.

(a) 90 0 ​​ (b) 60 0​​  (c) 45 0​​  (d) 30 0 ​​ 

 ​​​​  ​​ ​​ ​​ ​​ ​​ ​​ ​​ ​​ ​​ ​​ ​​ ​​ ​​ ​​ ​​ ​​ ​​ ​​​​ 

41. Find the interquartile range of 1,3,4,5,8,9,10,11,12,14,16

(d) 9​​ 

42. Donations during the launching of a church project were sent in sealed envelopes. The table shows​​ the distribution of the amount of money in the envelopes.

How much was the total donation?

(a) N 26,792.00

(b)​​  N 26,972.00

(c)​​  N 62,792.00

(d)​​  N 62,972.00

WAEC GCE solution

 ​​ ​​ ​​ ​​ ​​ In the diagram, PQ is a straight line, (m+n)=110 0 , (n+r) = 130 0 ​​ and (m+r)= 120 0 , find the ratio of m:n:r.

44. If​​ x: y = 14 : 38 and​​ y: z = 13​​ : 49, find​​ x: z 

45. Find the mean deviation of 20, 30, 25, 40, 35, 50, 45, 40, 20 and 45.

46. M and N are two subsets of the universal set (U). if n(U)=48, n(M)=20, n(N)=30 and n(MUN)=40, find n(MՈN)’.

47. Express 0.612 in the form​​ x/y, where​​ x​​ and​​ y​​ are integers and​​ y≠0.

​​ (b)​​ 68/111​​

 (c)​​ 61/100​​ 

(d)​​ 21/33

 ​​ ​​ ​​ ​​ ​​ ​​ ​​ ​​ ​​ ​​ ​​ ​​ ​​ ​​ ​​ ​​ ​​ ​​ ​​ ​​ ​​ ​​ ​​ ​​ ​​ ​​ ​​ ​​ ​​ ​​ ​​ ​​ ​​ ​​ ​​ ​​ ​​ ​​ ​​ ​​ ​​ ​​ ​​ ​​ ​​ ​​ ​​ ​​ ​​ ​​ ​​ ​​ ​​ ​​ ​​ ​​ ​​ ​​ ​​ ​​ ​​ ​​​​ 

waec mathematics

In the diagram, PQ//RS. Find​​ xx​​ in terms of​​ y​​ and​​ z.

(a)x=240 0​​  +  y- z ​​ 

(b)​​ x=180 0 ​​ + y- z ​​

 (c)​​ x=360 0 ​​ +  y- z​​ 

(d)​​ x=360 0 – y- z 

49. The diagonals of a rhombus WXYZ intersect at M. if​​ |MW|= 5 cm​​ |MX|= 5cm, calculate its perimeter.

(a) 42 cm  

(b)​​ 48cm​​ 

(c) 52​​ cm​​ 

(d)​​ 60​​ cm

50. The graphs of​​ y=  x 2 ​​ and​​ y=  x​​ intersect at which of these points?

(a) (0,0), (1,1)

(b) 0,0), (0,1)

(c) (1,0)(0,0)

(d)​​ (0,0)(0,0)​​ 

If you have any questions about  WAEC GCE Mathematics Questions and Answers 2023 , kindly drop your questions in the comment box.

Last Updated on October 2, 2023 by Admin

Related posts:

NECO logo

119 thoughts on “WAEC GCE Mathematics Questions and Answers for 2023/2024 (Theory and Objectives)”

Please I need gce maths question

Theory question

Question for GCE needed pls

please I need mathematics GCE questions 2023

Please the theory question

Pls I need the theory question and answer

Please gce for 2023

Pls objectives answer

Leave a Comment Cancel reply

Save my name, email, and website in this browser for the next time I comment.

Notify me of follow-up comments by email.

Notify me of new posts by email.

DMCA.com Protection Status

Watch CBS News

Teens come up with trigonometry proof for Pythagorean Theorem, a problem that stumped math world for centuries

By Bill Whitaker

May 5, 2024 / 7:00 PM EDT / CBS News

As the school year ends, many students will be only too happy to see math classes in their rearview mirrors. It may seem to some of us non-mathematicians that geometry and trigonometry were created by the Greeks as a form of torture, so imagine our amazement when we heard two high school seniors had proved a mathematical puzzle that was thought to be impossible for 2,000 years. 

We met Calcea Johnson and Ne'Kiya Jackson at their all-girls Catholic high school in New Orleans. We expected to find two mathematical prodigies.

Instead, we found at St. Mary's Academy , all students are told their possibilities are boundless.

Come Mardi Gras season, New Orleans is alive with colorful parades, replete with floats, and beads, and high school marching bands.

In a city where uniqueness is celebrated, St. Mary's stands out – with young African American women playing trombones and tubas, twirling batons and dancing - doing it all, which defines St. Mary's, students told us.

Junior Christina Blazio says the school instills in them they have the ability to accomplish anything. 

Christina Blazio: That is kinda a standard here. So we aim very high - like, our aim is excellence for all students. 

The private Catholic elementary and high school sits behind the Sisters of the Holy Family Convent in New Orleans East. The academy was started by an African American nun for young Black women just after the Civil War. The church still supports the school with the help of alumni.

In December 2022, seniors Ne'Kiya Jackson and Calcea Johnson were working on a school-wide math contest that came with a cash prize.

Ne'Kiya Jackson and Calcea Johnson

Ne'Kiya Jackson: I was motivated because there was a monetary incentive.

Calcea Johnson: 'Cause I was like, "$500 is a lot of money. So I-- I would like to at least try."

Both were staring down the thorny bonus question.

Bill Whitaker: So tell me, what was this bonus question?

Calcea Johnson: It was to create a new proof of the Pythagorean Theorem. And it kind of gave you a few guidelines on how would you start a proof.

The seniors were familiar with the Pythagorean Theorem, a fundamental principle of geometry. You may remember it from high school: a² + b² = c². In plain English, when you know the length of two sides of a right triangle, you can figure out the length of the third.

Both had studied geometry and some trigonometry, and both told us math was not easy. What no one told  them  was there had been more than 300 documented proofs of the Pythagorean Theorem using algebra and geometry, but for 2,000 years a proof using trigonometry was thought to be impossible, … and that was the bonus question facing them.

Bill Whitaker: When you looked at the question did you think, "Boy, this is hard"?

Ne'Kiya Jackson: Yeah. 

Bill Whitaker: What motivated you to say, "Well, I'm going to try this"?

Calcea Johnson: I think I was like, "I started something. I need to finish it." 

Bill Whitaker: So you just kept on going.

Calcea Johnson: Yeah.

For two months that winter, they spent almost all their free time working on the proof.

CeCe Johnson: She was like, "Mom, this is a little bit too much."

CeCe and Cal Johnson are Calcea's parents.

CeCe Johnson:   So then I started looking at what she really was doing. And it was pages and pages and pages of, like, over 20 or 30 pages for this one problem.

Cal Johnson: Yeah, the garbage can was full of papers, which she would, you know, work out the problems and-- if that didn't work she would ball it up, throw it in the trash. 

Bill Whitaker: Did you look at the problem? 

Neliska Jackson is Ne'Kiya's mother.

Neliska Jackson: Personally I did not. 'Cause most of the time I don't understand what she's doing (laughter).

Michelle Blouin Williams: What if we did this, what if I write this? Does this help? ax² plus ….

Their math teacher, Michelle Blouin Williams, initiated the math contest.

Michelle Blouin Williams

Bill Whitaker: And did you think anyone would solve it?

Michelle Blouin Williams: Well, I wasn't necessarily looking for a solve. So, no, I didn't—

Bill Whitaker: What were you looking for?

Michelle Blouin Williams: I was just looking for some ingenuity, you know—

Calcea and Ne'Kiya delivered on that! They tried to explain their groundbreaking work to 60 Minutes. Calcea's proof is appropriately titled the Waffle Cone.

Calcea Johnson: So to start the proof, we start with just a regular right triangle where the angle in the corner is 90°. And the two angles are alpha and beta.

Bill Whitaker: Uh-huh

Calcea Johnson: So then what we do next is we draw a second congruent, which means they're equal in size. But then we start creating similar but smaller right triangles going in a pattern like this. And then it continues for infinity. And eventually it creates this larger waffle cone shape.

Calcea Johnson: Am I going a little too—

Bill Whitaker: You've been beyond me since the beginning. (laughter) 

Bill Whitaker: So how did you figure out the proof?

Ne'Kiya Jackson: Okay. So you have a right triangle, 90° angle, alpha and beta.

Bill Whitaker: Then what did you do?

Bill Whitaker with Calcea Johnson and Ne'Kiya Jackson

Ne'Kiya Jackson: Okay, I have a right triangle inside of the circle. And I have a perpendicular bisector at OP to divide the triangle to make that small right triangle. And that's basically what I used for the proof. That's the proof.

Bill Whitaker: That's what I call amazing.

Ne'Kiya Jackson: Well, thank you.

There had been one other documented proof of the theorem using trigonometry by mathematician Jason Zimba in 2009 – one in 2,000 years. Now it seems Ne'Kiya and Calcea have joined perhaps the most exclusive club in mathematics. 

Bill Whitaker: So you both independently came up with proof that only used trigonometry.

Ne'Kiya Jackson: Yes.

Bill Whitaker: So are you math geniuses?

Calcea Johnson: I think that's a stretch. 

Bill Whitaker: If not genius, you're really smart at math.

Ne'Kiya Jackson: Not at all. (laugh) 

To document Calcea and Ne'Kiya's work, math teachers at St. Mary's submitted their proofs to an American Mathematical Society conference in Atlanta in March 2023.

Ne'Kiya Jackson: Well, our teacher approached us and was like, "Hey, you might be able to actually present this," I was like, "Are you joking?" But she wasn't. So we went. I got up there. We presented and it went well, and it blew up.

Bill Whitaker: It blew up.

Calcea Johnson: Yeah. 

Ne'Kiya Jackson: It blew up.

Bill Whitaker: Yeah. What was the blowup like?

Calcea Johnson: Insane, unexpected, crazy, honestly.

It took millenia to prove, but just a minute for word of their accomplishment to go around the world. They got a write-up in South Korea and a shout-out from former first lady Michelle Obama, a commendation from the governor and keys to the city of New Orleans. 

Bill Whitaker: Why do you think so many people found what you did to be so impressive?

Ne'Kiya Jackson: Probably because we're African American, one. And we're also women. So I think-- oh, and our age. Of course our ages probably played a big part.

Bill Whitaker: So you think people were surprised that young African American women, could do such a thing?

Calcea Johnson: Yeah, definitely.

Ne'Kiya Jackson: I'd like to actually be celebrated for what it is. Like, it's a great mathematical achievement.

Achievement, that's a word you hear often around St. Mary's academy. Calcea and Ne'Kiya follow a long line of barrier-breaking graduates. 

The late queen of Creole cooking, Leah Chase , was an alum. so was the first African-American female New Orleans police chief, Michelle Woodfork …

And judge for the Fifth Circuit Court of Appeals, Dana Douglas. Math teacher Michelle Blouin Williams told us Calcea and Ne'Kiya are typical St. Mary's students.  

Bill Whitaker: They're not unicorns.

Michelle Blouin Williams: Oh, no no. If they are unicorns, then every single lady that has matriculated through this school is a beautiful, Black unicorn.

Pamela Rogers: You're good?

Pamela Rogers, St. Mary's president and interim principal, told us the students hear that message from the moment they walk in the door.

St. Mary's Academy president and interim principal Pamela Rogers

Pamela Rogers: We believe all students can succeed, all students can learn. It does not matter the environment that you live in. 

Bill Whitaker: So when word went out that two of your students had solved this almost impossible math problem, were they universally applauded?

Pamela Rogers: In this community, they were greatly applauded. Across the country, there were many naysayers.

Bill Whitaker: What were they saying?

Pamela Rogers: They were saying, "Oh, they could not have done it. African Americans don't have the brains to do it." Of course, we sheltered our girls from that. But we absolutely did not expect it to come in the volume that it came.  

Bill Whitaker: And after such a wonderful achievement.

Pamela Rogers: People-- have a vision of who can be successful. And-- to some people, it is not always an African American female. And to us, it's always an African American female.

Gloria Ladson-Billings: What we know is when teachers lay out some expectations that say, "You can do this," kids will work as hard as they can to do it.

Gloria Ladson-Billings, professor emeritus at the University of Wisconsin, has studied how best to teach African American students. She told us an encouraging teacher can change a life.

Bill Whitaker: And what's the difference, say, between having a teacher like that and a whole school dedicated to the excellence of these students?

Gloria Ladson-Billings: So a whole school is almost like being in Heaven. 

Bill Whitaker: What do you mean by that?

Bill Whitaker and Gloria Ladson-Billings

Gloria Ladson-Billings: Many of our young people have their ceilings lowered, that somewhere around fourth or fifth grade, their thoughts are, "I'm not going to be anything special." What I think is probably happening at St. Mary's is young women come in as, perhaps, ninth graders and are told, "Here's what we expect to happen. And here's how we're going to help you get there."

At St. Mary's, half the students get scholarships, subsidized by fundraising to defray the $8,000 a year tuition. Here, there's no test to get in, but expectations are high and rules are strict: no cellphones, modest skirts, hair must be its natural color.

Students Rayah Siddiq, Summer Forde, Carissa Washington, Tatum Williams and Christina Blazio told us they appreciate the rules and rigor.

Rayah Siddiq: Especially the standards that they set for us. They're very high. And I don't think that's ever going to change.

Bill Whitaker: So is there a heart, a philosophy, an essence to St. Mary's?

Summer Forde: The sisterhood—

Carissa Washington: Sisterhood.

Tatum Williams: Sisterhood.

Bill Whitaker: The sisterhood?

Voices: Yes.

Bill Whitaker: And you don't mean the nuns. You mean-- (laughter)

Christina Blazio: I mean, yeah. The community—

Bill Whitaker: So when you're here, there's just no question that you're going to go on to college.

Rayah Siddiq: College is all they talk about. (laughter) 

Pamela Rogers: … and Arizona State University (Cheering)

Principal Rogers announces to her 615 students the colleges where every senior has been accepted.

Bill Whitaker: So for 17 years, you've had a 100% graduation rate—

Pamela Rogers: Yes.

Bill Whitaker: --and a 100% college acceptance rate?

Pamela Rogers: That's correct.

Last year when Ne'Kiya and Calcea graduated, all their classmates went to college and got scholarships. Ne'Kiya got a full ride to the pharmacy school at Xavier University in New Orleans. Calcea, the class valedictorian, is studying environmental engineering at Louisiana State University.

Bill Whitaker: So wait a minute. Neither one of you is going to pursue a career in math?

Both: No. (laugh)

Calcea Johnson: I may take up a minor in math. But I don't want that to be my job job.

Ne'Kiya Jackson: Yeah. People might expect too much out of me if (laugh) I become a mathematician. (laugh)

But math is not completely in their rear-view mirrors. This spring they submitted their high school proofs for final peer review and publication … and are still working on further proofs of the Pythagorean Theorem. Since their first two …

Calcea Johnson: We found five. And then we found a general format that could potentially produce at least five additional proofs.

Bill Whitaker: And you're not math geniuses?

Bill Whitaker: I'm not buying it. (laughs)

Produced by Sara Kuzmarov. Associate producer, Mariah B. Campbell. Edited by Daniel J. Glucksman.

Bill Whitaker

Bill Whitaker is an award-winning journalist and 60 Minutes correspondent who has covered major news stories, domestically and across the globe, for more than four decades with CBS News.

More from CBS News

Americans are choking on surging fast-food prices

3 times to buy long-term care insurance at 65 (and 3 times not to)

Mom accused of throwing son to his death in crocodile-infested canal

Heineken vows nearly $50 million to transform "tired pubs" in U.K.

EXPOLOADED

WAEC NECO JAMB GCE AND NABTEB QUESTIONS AND ANSWERS.

mathematics objective and essay

NECO 2018 EXPO General Mathematics Objective & Essay Questions AND Answers

donbaba Uncategorized 0

neco 2018 Mathematics Expo Answer, neco Maths Expo Answer 2018, 2018 neco Mathematics answer expo, 2018 neco Mathematics Questions, 2018/2019 neco maths Expo Runs, 2018 neco Mathematics Obj and Theory Expo, 2018 neco Mathematics Question and answer.. neco 2018 Mathematics Expo Answer, neco 2018 Maths Expo Answer, neco 2018 Mathematics Answer, neco Mathematics expo 2018, FREE neco Mathematics Answer 2018, FREE EXPO ON Mathematics neco, neco 2018 EXPO FOR FREE, FREE Mathematics neco ANSWERS, Mathematics QUESTIONS FOR neco, 2018 Neco ANSWERS, neco 2018 Mathematics EXPO ANSWERS,Mathematics neco RUNS, FREE neco Maths mathematics expo answers

HOW TO SUBSCRIBE NECO 2018 MATHEMATICS EXPO and GET ANSWERS 6HRS BEFORE EXAM STARTS.!! NOTE: WE WON’T POST MATHEMATICS ANSWERS FOR FREE, IF YOU DON’T SUBSCRIBE, YOU’LL BE LEFT ALONE TO DO IT YOURSELF!! Dont Pass Alone.

Invite Your Friends And Enemies Here Also For Them To Subscribe And Pass This MATHEMATICS Once.[A1 GUARANTEED] We Make It Hot Here… ↓ MATHEMATICS QUESTIONS AND ANSWERS NOW AVAILABLE WITH US

Welcome To The Right Source Once Again,Make Sure You Subscribe Here With Us To Smash A1 In This NECO 2018 MATHEMATICS ‎ ‎ …We Dont Need To Talk Much… THOSE THAT SUBSCRIBED WITH US REGULARLY ALREADY KNOW HOW WE ROLL…‎ EXPOLOADED.COM NONI.. Special Package‎ ‎ 2018 NECO MATHEMATICS RUNZ Subscribe For MATHEMATICS Early To Get Registered Early .

‎ Good News:‎ TELL YOUR FRIENDS THAT‎ WWW.EXPOLOADED.COM HAVE NECO‎ MATHEMATICS ANSWERS AND WILL‎ BE POSTED/SENT BY 11-12AM SUNDAY MIDNITE.

Dnt miss it

MATHEMATICS QUESTIONS IS NOW READY!‎ ENSURE YOU SUBSCRIBE TO GET IT BEFORE TIME 11-12AM MIDNITE‎ DIRECT => N1000MTNCARD PASSWORD/WHATSAPP => N500MTNCARD

FORWARD THE MTN CARD, YOUR‎ NAME, YOUR SUBJECT AND PHONE‎ NUMBER TO => 09030889003 ====== TRANSFER IS ALLOWED… ‎ Please Don’t Call Just Send Your Details Because The Number Might be Switched Off/Divert Due to Too Much Calls.

KEEP YOUR CARDS SAFE UNTILL U RECIEVE A CONFIRMATION TEXT. °°°°°°°°°°°°°°°°°° I swear we are not going to post‎ MATHEMATICS answers for free!! Alot of websites will post fake answers just to be famous like us. If you like copy those answers……‎ ‎ You Are On Your Own Oh!! We Remains The Best . EXPOLOADED.COM Academic Team GOODLUCK!! °°°°°°°°°°°°°°°‎ ‎ FREE NECO EXPO MATHEMATICS QUESTIONS AND ANSWERS

Neco Mathematics Expo Obj & Essay, Theory 2018 Mathematics Neco Expo 2018 Neco Mathematics Theory 2018 Neco Maths Expo 2018 Free NECO Mathematics Questions 2018 | NECO Mathematics OBJ and THEORY Answers. Mathematics, Mathematics NECO Expo Runs 2018 NECO 2018 Mathematics questions and answers to objectives and Theory questions Neco Mathematics Obj & Theory/Essay Answers 2018 (NECO MATHS EXPO) NECO 2018 Mathematics Expo Answer , NECO Maths Expo Answer 2018, 2018 neco Mathematics answer expo obj and essay Answers for Mathematics Obj & Theory, Essay – NECO

Share this:

Be the first to comment, leave a reply cancel reply.

Your email address will not be published.

Save my name, email, and website in this browser for the next time I comment.

This site uses Akismet to reduce spam. Learn how your comment data is processed .

Copyright © 2024 | WordPress Theme by MH Themes

IMAGES

  1. Essay 'Importance Of Mathematics In The Modern World'

    mathematics objective and essay

  2. Importance Of Math Essay

    mathematics objective and essay

  3. IB Math Extended Essay Topics: 20+ Ideas for Inspiration

    mathematics objective and essay

  4. Mathematics Day Essay

    mathematics objective and essay

  5. Writing Specific Objectives in Mathematics ppt

    mathematics objective and essay

  6. Use of Mathematics in Daily Life Essay

    mathematics objective and essay

VIDEO

  1. April 5, 2024

  2. #mathematics #essay #tricks #reasoning multiple 🤔🧐

  3. eye bother nail funny objective essay counter

  4. Mathematics objective question by SKG MATHS CLASS 10TH #viral #shortvideo #skgsir #mathematics #skg

  5. Mathematics objective questions ( set 1 set 2) #cbse maths answer key 2024

  6. mathematics objective question by SKG MATHS CLASS 10TH #viral #shortvideo #mathematics #trendingshor

COMMENTS

  1. NECO Mathematics Objective and Essay 2023 Questions & Answers: OBJ

    The NECO Mathematics Objective and Essay 2023 Questions and Answers provided in this guide serve as a valuable revision tool to help you prepare for the upcoming exam. Remember to practice regularly, seek clarification when needed, and manage your time effectively during the exam. With dedication and thorough preparation, you can excel in the ...

  2. WAEC GCE Mathematics Question and Answers 2023: Objective "OBJ" And Essay

    The WAEC GCE Mathematics examination will consist of two papers: Paper 1, which is the objective section, and Paper 2, which is the essay section. Here is the schedule for the 2023 WAEC GCE Mathematics exam: Paper 2 (Essay): This paper will start at 9:30 am and last for 2 hours 30 minutes. Paper 1 (Objective): This paper will commence at 2:00 ...

  3. Essay on Importance of Mathematics in our Daily Life in 100, 200, and

    Q.2. How mathematics is useful in our daily life essay? Ans: Mathematics, as a subject, is one of the most important subjects in our lives. Irrespective of the field, mathematics is essential in it. Be it physics, chemistry, accounts, etc. mathematics is there. The use of mathematics proceeds in our daily life to a major extent.

  4. Solved WAEC Mathematics Questions And Answers For 2023/2024 (Essay And

    The General Mathematics essay and objective paper for the West African Examination Council (WAEC) will now be written on Thursday, 1st June 2023. ... The WAEC Maths 2 (Essay) exam will begin at 9:30 am and last for 2 hours and thirty minutes, while the Waec Mathematics 1 (Objective) exam will begin at 3:00 pm and last for one hour and thirty ...

  5. WAEC Mathematics Questions and Answers 2023 Objective and Theory

    See WAEC mathematics objective and essay questions and answers below. WAEC Mathematics Answers 2023 Objective and Theory. The West Africa Examinations Council (WAEC) is an examination body in Nigeria that conducts the Senior Secondary Certificate Examination and the General Certificate in Education in May/June and November/December respectively.

  6. WAEC Mathematics Questions and Answers 2022 Objective and Theory

    See WAEC mathematics objective and essay questions and answers below. WAEC Mathematics Answers 2022 Objective and Theory. The West Africa Examinations Council (WAEC) is an examination body in Nigeria that conducts the Senior Secondary Certificate Examination and the General Certificate in Education in May/June and November/December respectively.

  7. WAEC Mathematics Questions and Answers 2023 ( Maths Obj and Essay

    This sections contains the Waec mathematics essay and Obj questions and answers. We'll post the Mathematics answers right here on this page ones the exam starts. Maths Answers Loading…. (Keep refreshing) Don't miss this great opportunity. With our Runz, your success in this exam is 100% sure. Best of luck!

  8. Complete NECO 2023 Mathematics Questions and Answers (Essay and Objective)

    NECO 2023 Mathematics Questions and Answers (Essay and Objective):. The National Examination Council (NECO) is a Nigerian examination body that conducts the Senior Secondary Certificate Examination (SSCE) for students in their final year of secondary school.The Mathematics examination is one of the core subjects that students are required to take. In this blog post, we will provide you with ...

  9. WAEC Mathematics 2020 Answers Essay & Obj Questions Finally Out

    The WAEC Maths 2 (Essay) paper will start by 8:30 am and will last for 2hrs 30mins while the Waec Mathematics 1 (Objective) exam will commence at 4:00pm and will last for 1hr 30mins.

  10. WAEC Mathematics 2023 Essay/Objective Questions and Answers

    If you have any questions about the WAEC English theory & Obj 2023, kindly let us know in the comment box. In conclusion, the WAEC Mathematics Questions and Answers 2023 is a challenging one. However, if you're equipped with the knowledge of the most common questions, as well as an understanding of tips and tricks for acing the exam, there ...

  11. Waec 2022 Mathematics Questions And Answers|obj And Essay [2 June 2022

    The Weac mathematics question and answer 2021 for preparation towards Waec start exam paper 2 & 1: Essay & Objective which will commence from 9:30 am - 12:00 pm and end by 3:00 pm - 4:30 pm. In this post, we will be posting samples of the Waec mathematics questions for candidates that will participate in the examination.

  12. Objectivity in Mathematics, Without Mathematical Objects

    The role of mathematics in the sciences would suffer the same destiny in that scenario: if mathematics is not fundamentally a product of the evolutionarily developed proto-arithmetic, and possibly other proto-mathematical abilities, the success of mathematical applications in science could be either a coincidence or based on the conventionalist ...

  13. WAEC Mathematics Answers 2024 [Essay/OBJ] Questions is Out

    The West African Examination Council (WAEC) General Mathematics essay and objective paper will now be written on Saturday, 25th November 2023. The WAEC Mathematics 2 (Essay) paper will start at 9:30 am and will last for 2hrs 30mins while the Waec Mathematics 1 (Objective) exam will commence at 2:00 pm and will last for 1hr 30mins.

  14. 2021-2022 WAEC PAST QUESTIONS on Further Mathematics: Objectives and

    2021/2022 WAEC Further Mathematics Questions and Answers Symbols used: ^ means raise to power / division. The Further Mathematics examination paper is going to comprise of two papers. Paper 1: Essay Paper 2: Objectives And, PAPER 1: will consist of forty multiple-choice objective questions, covering the entire Futher Mathematics syllabus.

  15. 2022 WAEC GCE Mathematics Questions and Answers

    NOTE: If You Want us To Assist You In Supplying Night Questions and Answers For The 2022 Waec Gce Second series Mathematics Essay And Objectives (obj) Questions and Answers Runz/Expo/dubs/chokes. You will Need to Subscribe with Us. We Have Two Ways of Sending questions and answers to Students,Teachers, Principals and School Owners.

  16. 2023 NECO: Mathematics Objectives and Essay Questions with Solutions

    2023 WAEC DATA PROCESSING Essay And Objectives ANSWERS; Animal Improvement: Definition, Aims, Processes, Advantages And Disadvantages. Agricultural Science Lesson Note. Farm Animal Parasites: Definition, Classification, Effects And Control Measures. Agricultural Science Lesson; 2023 WAEC Mathematics Questions And Solutions

  17. NECO Mathematics Questions and Answers 2022 Objective and Theory

    NECO Mathematics 2022 answers. NECO Mathematics questions and answers 2022/2023 objective and essay. See the 2022 NECO Mathematics answers for both objective and theory below. Get the NECO Mathematics objective and essay answers here. The 2022 NECO OBJ and theory questions and answers are provided here for free. All you have to do is to […] The post NECO Mathematics Questions and Answers ...

  18. 2022-2023 WAEC Mathematics Questions: Essay and Objectives with ANSWERS

    2022-2023 WAEC Mathematics Questions: Essay and Objectives with ANSWERS for easy go Evaluate 0.42 divided by 2.5 /0.5 x 2.05, leaving the answer in standard form. A. 1.639 x 10^2

  19. NECO Mathematics Questions and Answers 2023/2024

    NECO Mathematics Questions and Answers For Practice. The following NECO Maths questions are questions to expect in the 2023 NECO examination. The questions below are the NECO past questions and answers that will help you in your 2023 NECO Mathematics Questions. 1. Express the product of 0.09 and 0.06 in standard form. A. 5.4×10^-3. B. 5.4×10^-2.

  20. WAEC Further Mathematics 2023 Questions and Answer Obj and Theory

    Waec Further Mathematics Essay Questions; Waec Further Mathematics Objectives Questions, You will be writing two papers in a single day. In this article the previous year's Waec questions and the correct answers for Further Mathematics are released and the 2023 Waec Further Maths Exam Questions will also be made available to those who will be ...

  21. WAEC Further Mathematics Questions and Answers 2023/2024 (Objectives

    The Further Mathematics examination paper is going to comprise of two papers. Paper 1: Essay. Paper 2: Objectives. PAPER 1: will consist of forty multiple-choice objective questions, covering the entire Further Mathematics syllabus. Candidates will be required to answer all questions in 1 hour for 40 marks.

  22. WAEC GCE Mathematics Questions and Answers for 2023/2024 ...

    Find the value of p. (a) 1. (b) 2. (c) 3. (d) 9. Recommended: WAEC GCE Physics Questions and Answers. 23. The angle of elevation of the top of a tree from a point 27 m away and on the same horizontal ground as the foot of the tree is 30 0. Find the height of the tree.

  23. Home

    Show colleges you're ready. Learn about the SAT Suite of Assessments, which includes the SAT, PSAT/NMSQT, PSAT 10, and PSAT 8/9.

  24. Teens come up with trigonometry proof for Pythagorean Theorem, a

    Teens surprise math world with Pythagorean Theorem trigonometry proof | 60 Minutes 13:19. As the school year ends, many students will be only too happy to see math classes in their rearview mirrors.

  25. NECO 2018 EXPO General Mathematics Objective & Essay Questions AND

    NABTEB. NECOGCE 2024 ASSISTANCE. WAECGCE 2024 ASSISTANCE. 100% NECO 2024 RUNZ/EXPO. GET WAEC 2024 QUESTIONS AND ANSWERS 6HOURS BEFORE EXAM. FOR ADVERTISEMENT 09030889003 (WHATSAPP ONLY!!!) CLICK HERE FOR OUR ANSWER LINK. CONTACT US: 09030889003 (WHATSAPP ONLY)